(…) for the good and the beautiful are the beginning both of the knowledge and of the movement of many things. Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1013a 22–3
The ongoing battle against the reductionism of science over the last few decades has already brought many important changes in the scientific paradigm. Those changes are probably most transparent in biology, as it is concerned, by definition, with complex structures of living organisms. The rapid development of biochemistry and molecular biology has led some scientists to believe that their reductionist approach will prove to be the only valuable and truly “scientific” method of biological research. Contrary to these expectations, our ability to enter the molecular level of organisms and biochemical processes has opened us to an incredible complexity of the structures, processes, and patterns of living organisms, and thus challenged the reductionist paradigm. The intrinsic interrelatedness of different components of natural processes, such as metabolic or cell signaling networks, and their influence on the behavior of organisms, have led many bio‐scientists not only to distinguish between various levels of organization of matter in biology, but also to propose a more holistic account and methodology in the sciences. This is precisely the approach of systems biology, which introduces the concepts of emergent properties and downward causation (DC).
This methodological nonreductionism of contemporary biology opens an interesting discussion on the level of ontology and the philosophy of nature. For it turns out that the theory of emergence (EM), and DC in particular, have some crucial ontological implications. What we face today is a new opening for arguments challenging not only methodological, but also ontological and causal reductionism. However, the whole discussion is complicated and nuanced, requiring a careful philosophical analysis before formulating any general conclusions.
This article will concentrate mainly on philosophical aspects of EM and DC. At first, we will present a general definition of EM, with a special emphasis on the role of emergent properties as a crucial aspect for the whole idea of EM (section 1). The main part of the article will be devoted to the problem of metaphysics of DC. In the second section we will examine the positions of those who seem to understand DC in terms of efficient causality. A question regarding their understanding of cause, things being caused, and the nature of DC, will be asked. The problems of circularity and incoherence, and their possible solutions, will be addressed. The issues of nonreductive physicalism and the problem of the violation of underlying physical laws will be examined as well. In the third section we will refer to those thinkers who perceive DC as an argument against causal monism in sciences. Possible ways of a retrieval of the Aristotelian formal cause and a new understanding of DC will be analyzed. Finally, we will try to name the challenges faced by those who want to follow this new Aristotelian interpretation of DC.
Defining Emergence
The history of the development of the concept of EM goes back to the nineteenth century. Achim Stephan locates its beginnings in the philosophy of J. S. Mill (1843) and G. H. Lewes (1875) who analyzed the so‐called “compositions of causes” and introduced the concept of emergent effects. After several decades, at the beginning of the twentieth century, emergentism reappeared in the philosophy of biology, in opposition to vitalism and mechanistic reductionism. Its major proponents, Samuel Alexander (), C. Lloyd Morgan (1923), and C. D. Broad (), were called “British Emergentists” (Stephan , 25–26). The third phase of the debate on the concept of EM brought much criticism and skepticism about its relevance, due to the antimetaphysical agenda of logical positivism and analytical philosophy, in the middle of the twentieth century, in both continental and American contexts. The fourth phase and the revival of emergentism coincides with the debate on the mind‐brain problem, and contributions to this debate brought by Mario Bunge (), Karl Popper and John C. Eccles (1997), Roger Sperry (), and J. J. C. Smart (), in particular. To all phases listed by Stephan we should add the fifth, current phase, which—besides the continuing research in brain studies—includes the discovery and description of emergent properties in other parts of molecular and systemic biology. Besides this, the contemporary research in emergent studies has been recently enriched by an important analysis of new philosophical and theological implications of EM.
This pluralism of different realms of science and knowledge referring to the concept of EM brings a pluralism of definitions and classifications of different types of emergent properties. Moreover, philosophical analyses and definitions of EM differ remarkably from the scientific ones. The former examine more speculative, ontological, and causal dimensions of the concept of EM, whereas the latter search for practical examples, limiting theoretical discussion to a minimum. Following the first, more theoretical and speculative path, we will now try to list the most important philosophical characteristics of EM, in order to locate the idea of DC in the broader context of the complex definition of EM, and to show its central meaning for the very doctrine of emergentism.
Emergence of Complex Higher‐Level Entities
The first characteristic of EM is thus defined by Jaegwon Kim: “Systems with a higher‐level of complexity emerge from the coming together of lower‐level entities in new structural configurations (the new ‘relatedness’ of the entities)” (1999, 20). What is important and emphasized by many authors, is that, thus understood, emergentism strives to follow the rules of physical monism, which assumes that all natural phenomena are explainable in terms of fundamental physical laws and structures. In other words, EM needs to be physically grounded. This ultimate physicalist ontology underlies especially the position of nonreductive physicalism, which is strikingly close to the theory of EM, often using the same language and argumentation (Kim , 128–33).
When speaking about EM in terms of new structural configurations and a new relatedness of emergent entities, Kim introduces the concept of levels of complexity. Claus Emmeche, Simo Køppe, and Frederic Stjernfeld offer an important attempt at ontological specification and classification of levels. The physical interdependence of levels is described ontologically as their “inclusivity.” The higher level being materially related to the lower one, does not violate its laws, but at the same time cannot be simply deduced from it. In this way, EM avoids both dualism and eliminativism. In terms of ontological priority and posteriority, Emmeche et al. thus describe the status of higher and lower levels:
[A] rational idea of levels must entail that the more basic levels are basic in the sense of the word that they are presupposed by the higher levels—but the word “basic” does not entail any ontological priority. The higher levels are as ontologically pre‐eminent as the lower ones, even if being presupposed by them, that is, they are defined by properties by special cases of the lower levels. In this respect, levels are ontologically parallel, but non‐parallel in so far as they coexist. (1997, 96, 105–13)
Emmeche et al. propose a basic classification of levels. They distinguish four “primary levels”: the physical, the biological, the psychological, and the sociological, suggesting that each one of them can be a base for various sublevels. For instance, the biological level can contain: the cell, the organism, the population, the species, and the community sublevels. They also clarify that the interlevel relations are “nonhomomorphic”
in the sense that the emergence of the biological from the physical level does not have the same complex of inter‐level relations of dependence as the emergence of the social and psychic levels from the biological one, due to the continuous mutual conditioning and interdependence between emergent psyche and sociality. (2001, 15)
Although the ontology of levels proposed by Emmeche et al. brings some important clarifications, Jaegwon Kim asks further questions concerning ontological levels that still remain unanswered:
[H]ow are these levels to be defined and individuated? Is there really a single unique hierarchy of levels that encompasses all of reality or does this need to be contextualized or relativized in certain ways? Does a single ladder‐like structure suffice, or is a branching tree‐like structure more appropriate? Exactly what ordering relations generate the hierarchical structures? (1999, 20)
Emergence of Higher‐Level Properties
The second characteristic of EM says that “All properties of higher‐level entities arise out of the properties and relations that characterize their constituent parts. Some properties of these higher, complex systems are ‘emergent,’ and the rest merely ‘resultant’” (Kim , 21). The idea of this central component of emergentism goes back to the philosophy of J. S. Mill and G. H. Lewes, who proposed a distinction between the effect of many causes being an algebraic or vector sum of the effects of each one of them (a homeopathic causal law), and the effect of many causes that cannot be summarized in this way (a heteropathic causal law). The former is the case of a resultant effect, while the latter definition describes an emergent property (Stephan , 27–8).
Jaegwon Kim notices that this characteristic of EM is related to the concept of supervenience (SUP), which simply states that the higher‐level properties of a system occur only if appropriate conditions are realized on the lower level. When describing SUP Kim lists three putative components of supervenient properties: covariance, dependency, and nonreducibility. He shows that covariance (indiscernibility in respect to the base properties entailing indiscernibility in respect to supervenient properties) is metaphysically neutral, whereas dependence suggests an ontological and explanatory directionality. Both are needed in order to describe supervenient relations. In addition, he refers to nonreducibility of the supervenient properties. They cannot be simply educed from their base properties. Because SUP is related to EM, nonreducibility is also an important characteristic of the latter.
The Unpredictability and Irreducibility of Emergent Properties
“Emergent properties are not predictable from exhaustive information concerning their ‘basal conditions.’ In contrast, resultant properties are predictable from lower‐level information” (Kim , 21). Kim distinguishes here between “inductive” and “theoretical” predictability. Knowing from experience (empirically) that the property E, emerged from a certain lower‐level property M, of a system S, at the time t, we are able to predict and formulate a general emergent law, which says, that whenever the system S instantiates the base condition M, the emergent property E will appear as well. This “inductive” predictability differs from the “theoretical” one. No matter how accurate and detailed our knowledge of S and M is, we cannot theoretically predict E. This unpredictability, says Kim, is due to either our not having the concept of E, before it actually occurs, or some possible changes in the microstructure of M, which, transforming it into M*, will cause the emergence of E*, instead of E (Kim , 8–9).
The rule of irreducibility can be thus formulated: “Emergent properties, unlike those that are merely resultant, are neither explainable nor reducible in terms of their basal conditions” (Kim , 21). Departing from the classic intertheoretical Nagelian reduction, which requires the use of “bridge laws,” Kim proposes a functional model of reduction, which consists of three steps: (1) E must be “functionalized,” that is it has to be construed or reconstrued as a property defined by its causal/nomic relations to other properties of S; (2) E must have its realizers among the properties of S, in other words, a property M, needs to be found, that instantiates E; (3) a theory needs to be found which explains how realizers of E perform their causal task. Kim shows that functionalization of a property is necessary and sufficient for reduction. As irreducible, an emergent property E is neither predictable nor explainable on the basis of properties of a given system S (1999, 9–18).
The Causal Efficacy of the Emergents
Any description of a property at any level of organization of matter cannot ignore the question of the causal contribution to ongoing processes of the world. That is why, after describing basic characteristics of emergent properties, Kim asks one more question, namely what they can “do,” after having emerged. For without any causal powers emergent properties would simply turn out to be epiphenomenal, and—as Samuel Alexander says—“undoubtedly would in time be abolished” (1920, 2:8). Addressing this question, Kim defines the last important feature of emergentism: “Emergent properties have causal powers of their own—novel causal powers irreducible to the causal powers of their basal constituents” (Kim , 22). Unlike upward causation (an instantiation of a higher‐level property by a lower‐level property), and same‐level causation, DC occurs when emergent higher‐level property causes the instantiation of a lower‐level property. As an example we may think of symbiosis in biological systems. As an emergent phenomenon it is not merely based on the properties of two different organisms. Its nature changes microstructure and physiology of each one of them, oftentimes making their existence possible in an environment which otherwise will be unfavorable.
DC is of a crucial importance for the whole concept of EM. Early versions of DC are present in writings of Alexander () and Morgan (1923). In the 1970s Roger Sperry and Donald T. Campbell presented a more advanced definition of DC. Recently, the concept has been discussed by many authors among natural scientists, philosophers, and theologians. We will refer to some of them in the next part of this article.
For many proponents of EM, DC became a criterion of distinction between its weak and strong forms. Weak EM is understood as a result of limits in our human analytic possibilities. With the development of our knowledge and cognitive skills this epistemic (and thus subjective) emergent properties may simply disappear. Strong EM, on the other hand, is objective, as it assumes an ontological change and an occurrence of DC of emergent properties (Van Gulick , 59–63). Philip Clayton rightly says that “weak emergence is the starting position for most natural scientists” (2006a, 27). It should not be a problem for contemporary science and philosophy of science to accept characteristics of relationships between lower and higher levels of organization of matter and the rule of SUP, described in sections “Emergence of Complex Higher‐Level Entities,” “Emergence of Higher‐Level Properties,” and “The Unpredictability and Irreducibility of Emergent Properties,” after they have rejected materialistic and mechanistic reductionism. However, the concept of strong EM and emergent properties exerting DC on the lower levels, from which they themselves have emerged, can be a challenge and a threat to contemporary science, especially to those who want to both avoid reductionism and keep a physicalist position (nonreductive physicalists). Moreover, the concept of DC raises some critical metaphysical questions which may deeply affect, or even discredit the whole concept of strong EM. We will now address these issues.
Metaphysics of Downward Causation
Formulating a precise definition of DC is problematic. Numerous attempts of various scientists and philosophers writing about EM and DC have failed to find a general and accurate definition so far. In order to find such a definition, one will have to answer three fundamental questions: (1) What is the cause in DC?, (2) What is being caused (acted upon)?, and (3) What is the nature of DC? In this part of the article, we will analyze different answers to these questions, given by various authors writing about EM and DC. We will also try to examine the position of those who seem to understand DC in terms of efficient causality.
What Is Causal in DC?
There are several answers to the question of what is a cause in DC. Some of them concentrate on the idea of “general principles” as having causal powers. When we go back to Donald Campbell, who was the first one to use the concept of DC back in the 1970s in the context of evolutionary biology, we will see that for him “a cause” in DC means some kind of a law, regularity, or principle, which can be understood as a general disposition of a “whole” such as “molecule, cell, tissue, organ, organism, breeding population, species, in some instances social system, and perhaps even ecosystem”:
Where natural selection operates through life and death at a higher level of organization, the laws of the higher‐level selective system determine in part the distribution of lower‐level events and substances. (1974, 179–80)
The position of Terrence Deacon is very similar. Defining the second‐order EM, he says that “The interaction dynamics at lower levels becomes strongly affected by regularities emerging at higher levels of organization” (2006, 130).
Those who emphasize dynamic aspects of EM and DC find “patterns of organization,” or “boundary conditions” to be causal. Michael Polanyi (1969) understands them as higher‐level principles controlling lower‐level processes. Alicia Juarrero (, 132–3) introduces the concept of “context‐sensitive constraints” in complex dynamic systems, which connect objects with their environments (systems), strengthening their embeddedness. She redefines the concept of constraints, used formally in Newtonian mechanics, and presents them not only as reducing alternatives, but also as producing new possibilities, similar to the position of Terrence Deacon (, 182–205; Deacon and Cashman , 199–202). Arthur Peacocke (, 273) uses “boundary conditions” language as well when defining whole‐part constraint (his name for DC). Nancey Murphy (, 229), George Ellis (, 115), and Paul Davies (, 49) hold similar positions. Davies and Ellis additionally introduce some new terms such as “complexity threshold” or “higher‐level structural relations.” Probably the most detailed description of causal potency of “patterns of organization” is offered by Robert Van Gulick (, 83) who defines their properties as follows:
-
Such patterns are recurrent and stable features of the world.
-
Many such patterns are stable despite variations or exchanges in the underlying physical constituents; the pattern is conserved even though its constituents are not (e.g., in a hurricane or a blade of grass).
-
Many such patterns are self‐sustaining or self‐reproductive in the face of perturbing physical forces that might degrade or destroy them (e.g., DNA patterns).
-
Such patterns can affect which causal powers of their constituents are activated or likely to be activated. A given physical constituent may have many causal powers, but only some subset of them will be active in a given situation. The larger (i.e., the pattern) of which it is a part may affect which of its causal powers get activated. (…) Thus the whole is not any simple function of its parts, since the whole at least partially determines what contributions are made by its parts.
-
The selective activation of the causal powers of its parts (4) may in many cases contribute to the maintenance and preservation of the pattern itself (2, 3).
Another set of answers given to the question of the causal factor in DC concentrates on concrete events and entities, rather than just “patterns of organization” or “boundary conditions.” Nancey Murphy goes back to the philosophical theologian Austin Farrer. Although he does not use the term DC, he talks in his 1957 Gifford Lectures about systems in which “the constituents are caught, and as it were bewitched, by large patterns of action” (Farrer , 57). As we can see, it is a concrete action (event) that has a causal power in Farrer's description. When formulating a definition of the dynamic third‐order EM and its causal factors, Terrence Deacon follows Farrer's way of argumentation. Using the event descriptive terminology, he talks about “a higher‐order stochastic process extending across time that—like the limited stochastic processes of thermodynamics and morphodynamics—is capable of both cancelling and amplifying biases” (2006, 137). Again, we have here events (stochastic processes) that are regarded as causal factors.
Commenting on Farrer's thought, Nancey Murphy goes further and talks about “entities that exhibit new causal powers (or, perhaps better, participate in new causal processes or fulfill new causal roles) that cannot be reduced to the combined effects of lower‐level causal processes” (2007, 27). Emmeche et al. (, 18, 24) follow her ideas. Describing a strong and medium DC, they use a concept of an “entity or process,” ascribing to it causal properties, similar to the position of Sperry and Kim, who define certain properties of matter on higher levels of its organization as being causal with respect to properties of entities on lower levels (Stephan ). Thus they side indirectly with others who perceive concrete emergent entities as causes in DC, because the emergent properties in question have to be embedded in entities.
As we can see, there are many different ways of understanding a causal agent in DC, concentrating either on the concept of laws, general principles and patterns of organization, or referring to events and entities with their properties. This fact has deep metaphysical consequences. But before we analyze them, we will first address the problem of the other end of DC, namely the question of what is being caused (acted upon) in DC.
What Is Being Caused in DC?
Just like the attempt to arrive at a precise definition of the causal factor in DC, an attempt to specify the subject of this process (things being acted upon) brings plurality of answers. Most of the opinions can be classified according to the trifold division presented in Table .
As we can see, a careful analysis of theories of DC, in terms of both causal factors and things being caused, does not bring us to any clear and precise description and definition of this type of causality. Moreover, the plurality of answers on the level of the metaphysical constituents of DC indicates a deeper problem that presents a difficulty with understanding and defining the very nature of DC. We will now turn to this discussion, which is the core problem of emergentism.
The Nature of DC
The concept of DC in its contemporary version (beginning with Campbell and Sperry) is intrinsically connected with natural science and its methodology. It is our discoveries in physics, chemistry, and system biology in particular that have led us to discover complexities and properties that escape the description of basic‐level constituents of any given natural system. However, we cannot forget that the concepts of EM and DC are also philosophical, as they use terms such as entity, ontology, and causality. And here is the problem. For many proponents of emergent properties and their causal powers support at the same time—according to the first principle of EM described in section “Emergence of Complex Higher‐Level Entities”—the idea of the causal closure of physics and physical laws. This refers especially to those who identify themselves with nonreductive physicalism. But any philosophical reflection on physical causation, if permitted, restricts and constrains causality to efficient cause, based on the physical principle of action and reaction. (This position has been predominant in natural sciences since modernity.) Those who want to follow this line of argumentation, and to think about EM and DC in terms of causal closure of physics, face the problem of formulating not only a precise definition of a cause and things being caused in DC (see sections “What Is Causal in DC?” and “What Is Being Caused in DC?”), but also a definition of the nature of this kind of causation.
Our previous considerations show that there is a strong inclination (or at least a danger of such an inclination) among many proponents of EM to understand DC in terms of efficient causality. It is evident in the case of those who define both sides participating in DC as concrete events or entities with their properties. Those who find laws, general principles, and patterns of organization, as being causal, seem to be alluding to efficient causality as well. For in what way can a certain law, a general principle, or a pattern of organization of matter, have a causal influence on the lower‐level constituents? What kind of causation are we dealing with here? These questions remain unanswered in the case of many emergentists listed above.
The general problem of EM and DC understood in terms of efficient causality and in accordance with the principle of the causal closure of physics was described by Van Gulick as follows:
The challenge of those who wish to combine physicalism with a robustly causal version of emergence is to find a way in which higher‐order properties can be causally significant without violating the causal laws that operate at lower physical levels. On one hand, if they override the micro‐physical laws, they threaten physicalism. On the other hand, if the higher‐level laws are merely convenient ways of summarizing complex micro‐patterns that arise in special contexts, then whatever practical cognitive value such laws may have, they seem to leave the higher‐order properties without any real causal work to do. (2007a, 64–65)
To avoid this problem, Van Gulick proposes a new model in which higher‐order patterns involve the selective activation of lower‐order causal powers. But the question of the nature of DC still remains unanswered. If selective activation is a physical efficient cause, the whole argumentation falls into reductionism. If it is not a physical cause, the principle of physicalist ontology is violated.
Nancey Murphy (, 228; , 26–27) struggles with the same problem. Thinking of ontological aspects of EM and trying to define causal factors of emergent properties, she avoids the concept of new causal forces over and above those known to physics. Postulating them would again violate the causal closure of physics. She suggests instead approving the idea of new causal powers that cannot be reduced to the summary of lower‐level processes. But what is the nature of these causal powers? If they are not physical, how can they act upon physical constituents of lower levels? What is the “causal joint” between high and low levels of organization of matter? The nonphysical aspect of these causal powers seems to be contrary to the principle of the physical causal closure, emphasized in nonreductive physicalism.
Jaegwon Kim points to some other critical issues, faced by those who understand DC as a case of efficient causality (1999, 27). He emphasizes the fact that in DC higher‐level properties have to have a causal influence on their micro‐constituents. Thus understood, “reflexive downward causation” (a term coined by Kim) is combined with upward causation. Following Sperry, he gives an example of an eddy, which comes into being if, and only if, each and every molecule constituent to the puddle of water begins to move in an appropriate way. At the same time, it is the eddy that is moving all molecules around “whether they like it or not.” But here comes the question:
[H]ow is it possible for the whole to causally affect its constituent parts on which its very existence and nature depend? If causation or determination is transitive, doesn't this ultimately imply a kind of self‐causation, or self‐determination—an apparent absurdity? (1999, 28)
Kim adds that his reasoning implies a tacit acceptance of a metaphysical principle, which he calls “the causal‐power actuality principle”:
For an object, x, to exercise, at time t, the causal/determinative powers it has in virtue of having property P, x must already possess P at t. When x is caused to acquire P at t, it does not already possess P at t and is not capable of exercising the causal/determinative powers inherent in P. (1999, 29)
Kim embraces this principle, which is an expression of the transitive character of causation, and says that the circularity and incoherence threatening the plausibility of the whole concept of DC can be avoided only if we understand and define reflexive DC as diachronic. An introduction of a time delay between the cause and effect in DC is indispensable for him if we want to make it metaphysically plausible. He rejects synchronic DC saying that its coherence is doubtful.
But diachronic self‐reflective DC does not solve all problems for Jaegwon Kim. When applying EM to the mind‐body causation, he still finds it problematic, and claims that it eventually collapses into physicalism. He tries to show this by analyzing a theoretical example of an emergent mental property. We will try to summarize and illustrate his argumentation using a concrete example of a mental state of pain and escape reaction to it (see Figure ).
Kim tries to salvage DC and suggests giving it a “conceptual” interpretation. We can interpret higher levels as levels of concepts and descriptions, or levels characteristic for our representative apparatus, but not as levels of real phenomena and properties in the world. DC would then mean a cause described in terms of higher‐level concepts or higher‐level language, although it could be representable in lower‐level concepts and language as well. This approach will not save real DC—Kim admits—but it will save downward causal explanation, and maybe we should not expect anything more (1999, 33).
However, Kim's argumentation is vulnerable to critique. Alwyn Scott rejects his concept of diachronic DC, showing that from the nonlinear point of view the problem of circular causal loops and time in DC does not exist at all. According to Scott, an emergent structure does not pop into existence at time t. It “begins from an infinitesimal seed (noise) that appears at a lower level of description and develops through a process of exponential growth (instability). Eventually, this growth is limited by nonlinear effects, and a stable entity is established” (Scott , 287). Using Kim's notation applied in his “causal‐power actuality principle,” Scott depicts DC using nonlinear differential equations:
where x is an object, P is an emergent property, F and G are nonlinear functions of both x and P. The emergent structure is not represented by x(t) and P(t), but by x 0 and P 0, according to the following equations:
If x 0 and P 0 are asymptotically stable solution of the given system, we may assume that:
Because t → ∞ , what we are dealing with here is a dynamic balance between upward and downward causation. “Thus, Kim's causal‐power actuality principle—says Scott—is a theoretical artifact stemming from his static analysis of a dynamic situation” (2007a, 287). He then gives two examples of a simple and complex causal loops in the feedback mechanisms, to explain the relation between upward and downward causation (see Figure ).
The critique of Kim presented by Scott is justified and offers an answer to the problem of circular causal loops in DC. It also gives an argument against Kim's idea of diachronic reflexive DC. In terms of nonlinear causality, the problem of time simply disappears, and the whole concept of diachronic DC is needless.
However, we think that Scott's criticism of Kim does not address the key problem, which is the nature of DC. In his explanation of Figure b, Scott talks about entities which belong to different levels of both the biological and the cognitive hierarchies. They are entangled in a complex causal network. But what is the nature of causation between mental and biological entities? What is the causal joint between cognitive and physical structures? It seems to us that Scott is thinking in terms of efficient causality when presenting an example of a complex causal loop, in which various biological and cognitive properties are entangled. If this is the case, his explanation is insufficient.
The same criticism applies to Kim's argumentation reducing emergent properties and causality to the physical (Figure ). The downward causative feature of a mental property of pain (P) “standing” between two neural states (N and N1), and included in a regular efficient causal chain, would be truly superfluous, causing a problem of over determination. But the whole argumentation collapses once we acclaim that DC is not an efficient cause and cannot be understood in terms of this type of causality. But this would require a breakdown of causal monism in natural sciences, a departure from the position that science embraced and has protected ever since the scientific revolution in the modern era. Although for many it may not be an easy step to take, it seems that there is no other way to make the concept of DC plausible.
DC as Formal Cause
Those who manage to escape the narrow worldview of the scientific interpretation of the efficient causality are ready to begin their journey back to the notion of four distinctive modes of causality described by Aristotle. By no means is it an easy journey. The rejection of final and formal causality and the redefinition of the material cause became a heritage of modern science, and one of its most fundamental principles, affecting profoundly the mindset of many generations of scientists and philosophers. However, paradoxically, this same—natural science—becomes today more and more aware of many shortcomings of causal monism, thus opening anew the way for other types of causality.
Although this ongoing change in the relationship between natural science and philosophy of nature brings optimism and encouragement, we find ourselves witnessing its preliminary phase, knowing that much work remains to be done. Nonetheless, we believe that the whole discussion about DC is an important part of this process. In what follows we shall analyze the position of those who perceive DC as a formal cause, and address difficulties faced by those who would like to use Aristotle's division of causes in EM and DC.
Beyond Efficient Causality
We shall begin this part of the article with the trifold division of DC formulated by Emmeche et al. In their article published in 2001, Emmeche et al. present an original classification of different types of DC, based on a distinction between efficient and formal causality. The first type of DC in their classification is a strong downward causation (SDC). Its definition assumes an efficient causal influence of higher‐level entities on lower‐level entities. Moreover, it understands the former ones as being substantially different from the latter, and thus entails a substance dualism allowing for a violation of the assumption of the inclusivity of levels (see section “Emergence of Complex Higher‐Level Entities”). According to Emmeche et al., SDC is erroneous because, while assuming a real, existent chain of efficient causes, it locates this process in time, accepting the idea of exchange of energy between higher and lower levels as well. Their argumentation follows our critique of DC understood as efficient cause presented above (section “The Nature of DC”). Pointing out the problem of the causal joint between higher and lower levels, they show that it is not only SDC, but also strong upward causation that raises questions. For just as it is difficult to think of the biological level inflicting purely physical effects, the idea of physical cause having nonphysical efficient influence on higher level is also problematic. Thus, Emmeche et al. reject SDC and suggest that we should look for an understanding of DC beyond the idea of efficient causality.
At this point of their considerations, they introduce the idea of medium downward causation (MDC). In order to describe it they refer to the mathematical and physical language of differential equations describing the dynamics of systems. Using terms such as boundary (or constraining) conditions, they define MDC in terms of higher‐level entities as constraining conditions for the emergent activity of lower levels. In other words “the higher level is characterized by organizational principles—lawlike regularities—that have an effect (“downward,” as it were) on the distribution of lower level events and substances” (Emmeche et al. 2001, 25).
This definition reminds us of the whole group of authors to whom we referred in the second part of this article, who use the same language of boundary conditions and law‐like regularities in their description of the causal factor in DC (Juarrero, Peacocke, Murphy, Ellis, Davies, and others). But there is a substantial difference between them and Emmeche et al. who emphasize that
[M]edium DC does not involve the idea of a strict ‘efficient’ temporal causality from an independent higher level to a lower one, rather, the entities at various levels may enter part‐whole relations (e.g., mental phenomena control their component neural and biophysical sub‐elements), in which the control of the part by the whole can be seen as a kind of functional (teleological) causation, which is based on efficient, material as well as formal causation in a multinested system of constraints. (2001, 25)
What we find here is a retrieval of the Aristotelian fourfold division into material, formal, efficient, and final causality. An attempt to present Aristotle's position in details exceeds the scope of this article. Nevertheless, we should emphasize that he defined material cause not only in terms of particles understood as building blocks of entities, but also as a dynamic source of potentiality (primary matter). Formal cause for Aristotle is in turn something more than just a geometric shape of an entity. It is a principle of its actuality, that, by which a thing is what it is. His notion of efficient and formal cause is somewhat easier to grasp. The former one refers to the activity of an agent bringing a change, whereas the latter is understood by Aristotle as “that for the sake of which” a thing is done, a good proper for a being that can be attained (Aristotle ).
Even this short reference to the classical Aristotelian fourfold notion of causality shows that the position presented by Emmeche et al. needs further clarification and poses many questions (e.g., the question of the nature of the teleological and formal causation, and the question of the metaphysical status of a substance as a whole and the status of its components), nevertheless, the very fact of breaking the causal monism is significant, and that is why we strongly support Emmeche et al. when they say that
[T]here is a place for a rational concept of downward causation (in some version) in science and philosophy, but only with a broader framework of causal explanation. Very often ‘causality’ is implicitly equated with the usual notion of efficient causality, but if downward causation is regarded as an instance of efficient causality it will form a ‘strong version’ of the concept, which (…) is not a plausible one. The notion of causality should therefore be enlarged to make sense of downward causation. (2001, 17)
Finally, Emmeche et al. (2001, 26–31), using the phase‐space terminology, define weak downward causation (WDC), in which the higher level is the form into which the constituents of a lower level are arranged. In other words, the higher level is not a concrete substance, but an organizational level. The formal cause in WDC can be understood by analogy to the concept of “attractor” in a dynamical system that is a steady state toward which the system may evolve. The application of the formal causation in WDC is another example of a wider understanding of causality by Emmeche et al. Their position parallels that of Charbel N. El‐Hani and Antonio M. Pereira (, 127, 134–35), who emphasize the importance of the entanglement of matter and form, the role of higher‐order structures constraining lower ones, and the role of functional causation, in search for a middle road between reductionism and radical dualism.
Retrieval of Aristotle's Notion of Causality
The example of Emmeche et al. suggesting a return to the Aristotelian notion of causality is not an isolated one. There are several authors among “emergentists” taking similar position, although most of them do not develop this idea more broadly. Michael Silberstain, for instance, mentions at one point (with no further explanation) that
Systemic causation means admitting types of causation that goes beyond efficient causation to include causation as global constraints, teleological causation akin to Aristotle's final and formal causes, and the like. (Silberstein , 218)
Alvaro Moreno and Jon Umerez (, 107) also go back to Aristotle, arguing for an acceptance of a new type of causation in biological systems, which “is ‘formal’ in a sense that it infuses forms, i.e., it materially restructures matter according to a form.” But at the same time they claim that their position differs from the classical Aristotelian understanding of material and formal cause:
In Aristotle, both formal and material causes are intrinsic, whereas efficient and final ones are extrinsic. In our view of formal cause being efficient and being intrinsic do not exclude each other. In a sense, formal cause is intrinsic inasmuch as it is inherently generated in the very system which becomes an autonomous complex system. Anyway, formal cause can also be extrinsic with respect to some levels or subsystems (or even systems) which allow for relatively autonomous kinds of description. (2000, 107)
Alwyn Scott, in his introduction to The Nonlinear Universe (2007a, 5–7), presents a description of all four of Aristotle's causes. He also adds that, in modern terms, Aristotle's material and formal causes are put together and classified as “distal causes,” his efficient cause is called a “proximal cause,” while the final cause is given the name “teleological cause.” One can see the differences between his position and that of Moreno and Umerez.
Philip Clayton and Terrence Deacon go back to Aristotle as well. The former does it while explaining the historical trajectory of the conceptual foundations of EM theory (Clayton , 4–5). Deacon's approach is similar. He lists four Aristotelian causes and describes the process of a slow erosion of the plural notion of causality in the history of philosophy and science. This enhanced reductionism in which “only ‘pushes’ seem allowable as determinants of the efficacy and direction of physical changes” (2006, 113–14). But Deacon does not confine himself to historical references to Aristotle only. In fact, just as Emmeche et al. propose an application of Aristotelian causality in metaphysics of EM and DC, Deacon offers some interesting applications of formal and final causes in philosophy of biology (2006; 2011). When explaining the third‐order emergent dynamics, Deacon introduces the concept of specific “absences,” thus describing certain processes at higher levels of organization of matter:
This physical disposition to develop toward some target state of order merely by persisting and replicating better than neighboring alternatives is what justifies calling this class of physical processes teleodynamic, even if it is not directly and literally a ‘pull’ from the future.
[T]he ‘constitutive absences’ characteristic of both life and mind are the sources of this apparent ‘pull of yet unrealized possibility’ that constitutes function in biology and purposive action in psychology. The point is that absent form can indeed be efficacious, in the very real sense that it can serve as an organizer of thermodynamic processes (Deacon , 143–44).
We find in Deacon's ideas of “constitutive absences,” “efficacious absent forms,” and “teleodynamics” proposals for a new and original understanding of formal and final causation in biology. Clearly, the whole matter requires a careful analysis and study beyond the scope of this article. Nonetheless, a reference to Aristotle is apparent, and we think that Deacon's work opens a new possibility for a retrieval of all four of Aristotle's causes in philosophy of biology. Deacon himself thus concludes his description of the three orders of EM:
In many ways, I see this analysis of causal topologies as a modern reaffirmation of the original Aristotelian insight about categories of causality. Whereas Aristotle simply treated his four modes of causality as categorically independent, however, I have tried to demonstrate how at least three of them—efficient (thermodynamic), formal (morphodynamic), and final (teleodynamic) causality—are hierarchically and internally related to one another by virtue of their nested topological forms. Of course there is so much else to distinguish this analysis from that of Aristotle (including ignoring his material causes) that the reader would be justified in seeing this as little more than a loose analogy. The similarities are nonetheless striking, especially considering that it was not the intention to revive Aristotelian physics. (2006, 148)
Deacon's account of EM is somehow related to the idea of causally effective goals proposed by George Ellis (, 118–22). He sees them as central factors in feedback control systems, and ascribes to them causal properties which are the result of the information about the system's desired behavior or responses that they embody. For him, living systems are “teleonomic,” that is, goal‐seeking. Moreover, these goals are not the same as material states, although they are expressed and become effective in a material way. Ellis says that goals can be either: in‐built, as homeostasis; learned; or consciously chosen. Although he does not refer to Aristotle, his notion of causally effective goals resembles the Aristotelian final cause.
We could probably find some more examples of authors going back—directly or indirectly—to the classic Aristotelian understanding of causation. We find this tendency very promising from the perspective of philosophy of nature and metaphysics. It can serve as another powerful argument opposing the reductionist approach, still prevalent in science and philosophy of nature. However, this line of research is at its preliminary stage, and those who want to continue it will have to face some difficulties. What is more, the very idea of using Aristotle's notion of causality in the contemporary discussion of DC has already been criticized. We will close this article with a short analysis of this criticism, trying to show that it opens in fact some new perspectives for EM and DC theory understood in the light of the Aristotelian pluralistic notion of causality.
Perspectives for the Future
An attempt to bring the Aristotelian notion of causality back into discussion, made by Emmeche et al., has been criticized by Menno Hulswit. In fact, his comments seem to apply to other authors who are in favor of explaining DC as a type of formal causality as well. Hulswit begins his criticism by saying that Emmeche et al. show a strong bias toward thinking in terms of substances and substantial forms without presenting any arguments to explain and support this position (2005, 276). To that we answer that it is not possible to embrace Aristotle's view of causation without accepting his understanding of substance. However, we agree that this turn to substance metaphysics needs to be clarified and explained in more detail, in the context of the entire system of Aristotle's philosophy and contemporary science.
Hulswit continues his critical evaluation of DC by saying that Emmeche et al. are not consistent in their description of MDC. When formulating its definition they identify higher‐ and lower‐level entities as substances or substantial form, while later on, when giving some concrete examples of MDC, they refer to thoughts constraining neurological states and mental phenomena controlling their component neural and biophysical subelements. Neither of these can be treated as substances, according to Hulswit. What is more, the same criticism refers to processes and interactions (2005, 276–77). We find all these questions important and relevant. Answering them requires a detailed study of Aristotle's substantial metaphysics, his ideas of substance and its categories, substantial and accidental form, and substantial and accidental changes. Thus we agree that the ontological status of the causal relata in DC, understood in terms of formal causation, needs to be clarified.
Hulswit is also skeptical about the summary of Emmeche et al.'s exposition of medium and weak DC, in which they use the language of SUP:
The point of departure in both cases is the assumption of formal causality. As higher level entities (e.g., a cell) supervene on lower order entities (molecules), formal causality on the higher level supervenes on the efficient causality of the lower level. This can be interpreted as the selection—from a very large set of possible (efficient) interactions—of a small set of realizable (efficient) interactions on the lower level, on which the higher level then (formally) supervenes. In any case, in our view this is the only non‐contradictory version of downward causation possible. (Emmeche et al. 2001, 31–32)
We agree that this explanation of the nature of DC, based on the theory of SUP, is somehow unfortunate. As we have seen in the first part of this article, DC is more than just a relation of dependency between supervenient and subvenient properties (see sections “Emergence of Higher‐Level Properties” and “The Causal Efficacy of the Emergents”). The whole discussion shows that it is not only causal relata, but also the nature of DC understood as formal causation, that needs to be explained in more details. Otherwise, we may find ourselves helpless in the face of sharp criticism on the part of Menno Hulswit, who says that “the concept of ‘downward causation’ is muddled with regard to meaning of causation and fuzzy with regard to what it is that respectively causes and is caused in downward causation” (2005, 284).
In his article Hulswit presents one more critical argument, which is of a great importance for the whole debate. He contrasts the classical Aristotelian concept of formal cause with the modern concept of natural law. He claims that—although they have the same function, that is to explain the apparent stability of the world—they differ significantly, for
the formal cause was meant to explain the stability of the world in terms of the structure of things, whereas natural laws explain the stability of the world in terms of the dynamic relations between events. (2005, 278)
At this point we strongly disagree with Hulswit. His differentiation between the formal cause and natural laws presupposes a static interpretation of the Aristotelian metaphysic of substance, which is irrelevant. We should not forget that Aristotle's “Physics” and “Metaphysics” have their origin in the philosopher's reflection on both stability and the dynamic change of entities (substances) observed in the natural world. His philosophy of nature is by no means static. Thus we can see that an attempt to formulate a plausible account of DC explained in terms of formal cause will require a reconsideration of Aristotle's basic metaphysical assumptions and rediscovering the dynamic aspect of his thought.
To sum up, our analysis of Menno Hulswit's criticism of the work of Emmeche et al. appears to be very insightful. Although many of his questions and doubts are justified, they do not force a rejection of the whole idea. Quite the contrary; we find them setting a new stage for the future research and conversation about the metaphysics of DC interpreted in terms of formal causation. We hope to participate actively in this conversation, and search for answers to these and other questions concerning DC.
Conclusion
Witnessing scientists discovering complex structures (“wholes”) is really fascinating for a philosopher of nature in his encounter with contemporary science. The reductionist paradigm has been called into question, and seems to be losing its power. Our fascination with complexity of nature and multilayered irreducible structures of its organization requires from us a new and more holistic approach to the reality described in sciences. Philosophy of nature seems to be of a great help for all scientists who do not constrain themselves to the narrow perspective and terminology of their own field.
The theory of EM and DC appears to be a promising tool, opening a fruitful conversation between scientists, philosophers of nature, and philosophers of science. We hope that it will also bring us closer to a more holistic and integral understanding of the world, its structures and processes. However, we are aware of the fact that as interdisciplinary theories, both EM and DC raise many questions and require further study and clarification. This article shows that both sides of the dialogue (science and philosophy) are struggling in search for a proper and adequate language, which would help to explain EM and DC. We tried to prove that the language of efficient causality, which has been predominant in natural science since modernity is not sufficient any more. In opposition to causal monism, we suggested a return to Aristotle's language of plurality of causes. We believe this return is possible and rational, although our study shows that the way back may be long and challenging. But we should not be surprised. It is never easy to retrieve a language that has not been used for a long time.
Notes
- Philosophical aspects of EM will be discussed in this article. Its theological implications are presented and analyzed by Philip Clayton (), Michael Dodds (2012), Niels Henrik Gregersen (), John F. Haught (2007), Arthur Peacocke (), and William R. Stoeger SJ (). ⮭
- As an example, one can compare the following philosophical fourfold definition of EM presented in this chapter, with the one formulated by a biological anthropologist Terrence Deacon (, 122), who simply defines EM as “unprecedented global regularity generated within a composite system by virtue of the higher‐order consequences of the interactions of composite parts.” ⮭
- Kim says that it is best to separate the covariation element from the dependency in SUP, because it helps to understand that the covariation alone does not entail dependency. For him the question of what must be added to covariation to yield dependence remains an interesting and deep metaphysical question (1990, 5–23). ⮭
- See the summary in Nancey Murphy (, 28–29). ⮭
- To list some of the key thinkers addressing the problem of DC recently: David Chalmers (), Paul Davies (), Terrence Deacon (), George Ellis (), Claus Emmeche et al. (), Charbel N. El‐Hani and Antonio M. Pereira (), Menno Hulswit (), Robert Van Gulick (, 2007b), Alicia Juarrero (), Jaegwon Kim (), Alvaro Moreno and Jon Umerez (), Nancey Murphy (), Arthur Peacocke (), Michael Silberstein (), Alwyn Scott (2007a, 2007b). ⮭
- We are presenting an original argumentation by Kim but we have changed his literal symbols in order to apply them to the concrete example of pain and escape reaction. See Kim (, 31–33; 2006b, 557–58). ⮭
- Emmeche et al. (, 18–23). As an example of an erroneous understanding of DC as SDC, they refer to a living cell understood as an emergent entity. In literature a cell is described as causing changes in the molecules constitutive to it, making them specifically “biological,” substantially different from other molecules of the nonliving matter. “But if we imagine a microscopic view of this alleged causal process”—say Emmeche et al.—“we will be unable to find any effective causality in the scenario. First, the process does not take place in time; second, the two events in question do not even possess the ability of causing each other. Of course, it is evident that the biological cell ‘governs’ or ‘influences’ the biochemical processes taking place in it—but at the same time the cell remains in itself a biochemical construct. (…) The cell consists of biochemical processes, we could say, but this is a non‐temporal (mereological) relation and therefore non‐causal in the efficient‐causality use of the word. So even the idea of an upward efficient cause (or ‘strong’ upward causation) from biochemistry to cell is wrong because of this; what we could say instead is that the molecules and the biochemical reactions in questions constitute the cell, that is, they are the material and formal causes of the cell” (Emmeche et al. 2001). ⮭
- Deacon's remark about independency of causal modes in Aristotle is somehow mistaken. In Aristotle's biology, for instance, final causality is intimately related with formal (as in generation of offspring). ⮭
- Later on (p. 283) Hulswit talks about “Western ‘substance addiction’,” and refers to Bickhard and Campbell (2001), who argue that the Aristotelian substance ontology is “an inadequate metaphysics for relationships and process, most especially open process,” and claim that we should substitute it with a process metaphysics. As an example of process metaphysics applied in explaining emergent phenomenon of mind we can refer to David Griffin's Unsnarling the World‐Knot: Consciousness, Freedom, and the Mind‐Body Problem (2008). However, process metaphysics has its problems as well. According to Deacon, who is addressing the same problems as Griffin, panpsychic assumptions of process metaphysics do not explain “why the character of physical process associated with life and mind differs so radically from those associated with the rest of physics and chemistry—even the weird physics of the quantum” (2011, 79). ⮭
References
Alexander, Samuel. 1920. Space, Time and Deity. 2 vols. London: Macmillan. Retrieved November 7, 2012, fromhttp://books.google.com/books?id=gMYtAAAAYAAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=space,+time,+and+deity+vol+2&hl=pl&sa=X&ei=WjibUICVLOuvigKPlYGoCg&ved=0CC0Q6AEwAA#v=onepage&q&f=false
Aristotle. 2001. The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. RichardMcKeon. New York: The Modern Library.
Bickhard, Mark H., and Donald T.Campbell. 2001. “Emergence.” In Downward Causation: Minds, Bodies and Matter, ed. Peter BøghAndersen, ClausEmmeche, Niels OleFinnemann, and Peder VoetmannChristiansen, 322‐48. Aarhus, Denmark: Aarhus University Press.
Broad, C. D.1925. The Mind and Its Place in Nature. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Bunge, Mario. 1977. “Emergence and the Mind,” Neuroscience 2: 501–09.
Campbell, Donald T.1974. “Downward Causation .” In Studies in the Philosophy of Biology, ed. FranciscoJ. Ayala and T.Dobzhansky, 179–86. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Chalmers, David J.2006. “Varieties of Emergence .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 244–54. New York: Oxford University Press.
Clayton, Philip. 2006a. “Conceptual Foundations of Emergence Theory .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 1–31. New York: Oxford University Press.
Clayton, Philip. 2006b. “Emergence from Quantum Physics to Religion: A Critical Appraisal .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 303–22. New York: Oxford University Press.
Davies, Paul. 2006. “The Physics of Downward Causation .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 35–52. New York: Oxford University Press.
Deacon, Terrence. 2006. “Emergence: The Hole at the Wheel's Hub .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 111–50. New York: Oxford University Press.
Deacon, Terrence. 2007. “Three Levels of Emergent Phenomena .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 88–110. New York: Oxford University Press.
Deacon, Terrence. 2011. Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter. New York: W. W. Norton.
Deacon, Terrence, and T.Cashman. 2012. “Eliminativism, Complexity and Emergence .” In The Routledge Companion to Religion and Science, ed. JamesHaag, GregoryPeterson, and MichaelSpezio, 193–205. New York: Routledge.
Dodds, Michael J.2012. Unlocking Divine Action: Contemporary Science & Thomas Aquinas. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.
El‐Hani, Charbel Niño, and Antonio MarcosPereira. 2000. “Higher‐Level Descriptions: Why Should We Preserve Them ?” In Downward Causation. Mind, Bodies and Matter, ed. Peter BøghAndersen, ClausEmmeche, Niels O.Finnemann, and Peder VoetmannChristiansen, 118–42. Aarhus, Denmark: Aarhus University Press.
Ellis, George F. R.2006a. “On the Nature of Emergent Reality .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 79–107. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ellis, George F. R.. 2006b. “Physics, Complexity, and the Science‐Religion Debate .” In The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science, ed. PhilipClayton, 751–66. New York: Oxford University Press.
Ellis, George F. R.. 2007. “Science, Complexity, and the Nature of Existence .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, eds. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 113–40. New York: Oxford University Press.
Emmeche, Claus, SimoKøppe, and FredericStjernfeld. 1997. “Explaining Emergence: Towards an Ontology of Levels,” Journal for General Philosophy of Science 28(1): 83–119.
Emmeche, Claus, SimoKøppe, and FredericStjernfeld. 2001. “Levels, Emergence, and Three Versions of Downward Causation .” In Downward Causation. Mind, Bodies and Matter, ed. Peter BøghAndersen, ClausEmmeche, Niels O.Finnemann, and Peder VoetmannChristiansen, 13–34. Aarhus: Denmark Aarhus University Press.
Farrer, Austin. 1958. The Freedom of the Will. The Gifford Lectures. London: Adam and Charles Black.
Gregersen, Niels Henrik. 2006a. “Emergence and Complexity .” In The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science, ed. PhilipClayton, 767–83. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gregersen, Niels Henrik. 2006b. “Emergence: What is at Stake for Religious Reflection? ” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 279–302. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gregersen, Niels Henrik. 2007. “Reduction and Emergence in Artificial Life: A Theological Appropriation .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 284–314. New York: Oxford University Press.
Griffin, David. 2008. Unsnarling the World‐Knot: Consciousness, Freedom, and the Mind‐Body Problem. Eugene, OR: Wipf & Stock.
Haught, John. 2007. “Emergence, Scientific Naturalism, and Theology .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, eds. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 248–66. New York: Oxford University Press.
Hulswit, Menno. 2005. “How Causal Is Downward Causation?” Journal for General Philosophy of Science 36(2): 261–87.
Juarrero, Alicia. 1999. Dynamics in Action: Intentional Behavior as a Complex System. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kim, Jaegwon. 1990. “Supervenience as a Philosophical Concept.” Metaphilosophy 21(1, 2): 1–27.
Kim, Jaegwon. 1992. “‘Downward Causation’ in Emergentism and Nonreductive Physicalism .” In Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism, ed. AnsgarBeckermann, HansFlohr, and JaegwonKim, 119–38. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Kim, Jaegwon. 1999. “Making Sense of Emergence,” Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 95(1, 2): 3–36.
Kim, Jaegwon. 2006a. “Being Realistic about Emergence .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 189–202. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kim, Jaegwon. 2006b. “Emergence: Core Ideas and Issues,” Synthese 151(3): 547–59.
Lewes, G. H.. 1875. The Foundations of a Creed. 2 vols. Boston: Houghton, Osgood.
Mill, John Stuart. 1843. System of Logic. 2 vols. London: John W. Parker.
Moreno, Alvaro, and JonUmerez. 2000. “Downward Causation at the Core of Living Organization .” In Downward Causation: Mind, Bodies and Matter, ed. Peter BøghAndersen, ClausEmmeche, Niels O.Finnemann, and Peder VoetmannChristiansen, 99–116. Aarhus, Denmark: Aarhus University Press.
Morgan, C. Lloyd. 1923. Emergent Evolution. The Gifford Lectures. London: Williams and Norgate. Retrieved November 7, 2012, from http://www.giffordlectures.org/Browse.asp?PubID=TPEMEV&Volume=0&Issue=0&TOC=TRUE
Murphy, Nancey. 2006. “Emergence and Mental Causation .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 227–43. New York: Oxford University Press.
Murphy, Nancey. 2007. “Reduction – How Did We Fall into It and Can We Emerge From It? ” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 19–39. New York: Oxford University Press.
Peacocke, Arthur. 1991. Theology for a Scientific Age: Being and Becoming – Natural, Divine, and Human. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.
Peacocke, Arthur. 1995. “God's Interaction with the World: The Implications of Deterministic ‘Chaos’ and of Interconnected and Independent Complexity .” In Chaos and Complexity: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action, ed. Robert J.Russell, NanceyMurphy, and ArthurPeacocke, 263–87. Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory; Berkeley, CA: Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences.
Peacocke, Arthur. 2006. “Emergence, Mind, and Divine Action: The Hierarchy of the Sciences in Relation to the Human Mind‐Brain‐Body .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 257–78. New York: Oxford University Press.
Peacocke, Arthur. 2007. “Emergent Realities with Causal Efficacy: Philosophical and Theological Applications .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 267–83. New York: Oxford University Press.
Polanyi, Michael. 1969. Knowing and Being. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Popper, Karl R., and John C.Eccles. 1997. The Self and Its Brain. New York: Springer.
Scott, Alwyn C.2007a. The Nonlinear Universe. New York: Springer.
Scott, Alwyn C.. 2007b. “Nonlinear Science and the Cognitive Hierarchy .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 173–97. New York: Oxford University Press.
Silberstein, Michael. 2006. “In Defence of Ontological Emergence and Mental Causation .” In The Re‐Emergence of Emergence, ed. PhilipClayton and PaulDavies, 203–26. New York: Oxford University Press.
Smart, John J. C.1981. “Physicalism and Emergence,” Neuroscience 6: 109–13.
Sperry, Roger W.1980. “Mind‐Brain Interaction: Mentalism, Yes; Dualism, No,” Neuroscience 5: 195–206.
Stephan, Achim. 1992. “Emergence: A Systematic View on Its Historical Facets .” In Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism, ed. AnsgarBeckermann, HansFlohr, and JaegwonKim, 25–48. New York: Walter de Gruyter.
Stoeger, William R.2007. “Reductionism and Emergence: Implications for the Theology and Science Dialogue .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 229–47. New York: Oxford University Press.
Van Gulick, Robert. 2007a. “Reduction, Emergence, and the Mind/Body Problem .” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 40–73. New York: Oxford University Press.
Van Gulick, Robert. 2007b. “Who's in Charge Here? And Who's Doing All the Work? ” In Evolution and Emergence: Systems, Organisms, Persons, ed. NanceyMurphy and William R.Stoeger, 74–87. New York: Oxford University Press.