During a 1995 meeting of the Islamic Organization for Medical Sciences (IOMS), medical experts and Islamic jurisconsults deliberated on “Judically (sic) Prohibited and Impure Substances in Foodstuffs and Drugs” (Recommendations of the 8th Fiqh‐Medical Seminar ). The ethico‐legal discussions resulted in a religious decree that considered it permissible for Muslims to use medicines that contained “gelatin formed as a result of transformation…of a judicially impure animal (e.g., pig)” (Recommendations of the 8th Fiqh‐Medical Seminar ). Attending this meeting were several health policy stakeholders, including representatives of the World Health Organization (WHO). Motivated by a desire to “relieve all Muslims…from the embarrassment they feel” when taking medicines with porcine gelatin, WHO representatives disseminated the verdict widely (Gezairy ), and as a result vaccine advocates came to promote the Islamic permissibility of using vaccines with porcine components.
More than a decade later, in 2008, the Indonesian Ulema Council (MUI) issued a religious verdict declaring the GlaxoSmithKline (GSK) meningitis vaccine to be impermissible to use, ḥaram, because porcine was used in its production (Yessir ). Eventually the MUI permitted use of the vaccine by considering an extreme necessity, ḍarurah, to exist (Sagita ). This conditional permission was revoked in the following year when the MUI decreed the meningitis vaccines produced by Novartis and Tian Yuana to be porcine‐free and therefore ḥalal (Hapsari ; Jakarta Post ).
In this article, I examine the Islamic bioethical deliberations around the use of vaccines with porcine components from an applied Islamic bioethics perspective. More specifically, I seek to explore how ground‐level actors, in this case health policy stakeholders, utilized the aforementioned verdicts. Therefore I will begin by first reviewing the juridical decrees and then by recounting how several health policy stakeholders used these verdicts, by way of media reports and documents available in the public domain. My analysis will next highlight aspects of the particular Islamic ethico‐legal arguments noted by the juridical authorities in the final verdicts in order to illustrate more general concepts within Islamic law. I will argue that certain core elements of the Islamic ethico‐legal tradition were overlooked by policy stakeholders utilizing the IOMS verdict, and that these elements must be accounted for when using religious decrees to inform public policy. While Islamic juridical council deliberations are extensive, and their proceedings offer much insight into the fiqhi frameworks and deliberative processes used by jurists and the dissenting voices at the proverbial council table, such materials are not primary sources to understand the usage of the consensus final verdicts by Islamic bioethics consumers, nor are they easily accessible to nonjurist health professionals (by accessible I mean both in terms of physical access, and in terms of understanding). Since health policy actors seek and use verdicts, I restrict myself to pointing out the ethico‐legal frames and constructs noted in the final verdicts, where possible. I will conclude my commentary by offering several recommendations that may facilitate the more judicious use of verdicts in policy‐relevant Islamic bioethics discourse.
The Story
Part 1: The IOMS and Porcine Vaccines
The IOMS brings together medical scientists and Islamic jurisconsults from across the world to discuss the bioethical concerns of Muslim societies. They aim to address modern challenges from an Islamic perspective and perform collective ijtihad, Islamic ethico‐legal assessment, resulting in Islamic religious verdicts, qararat or fatawa. The deliberative councils are designed to be pluralistic and rigorous; they are comprised of prominent Islamic jurisconsults purposively chosen to represent many Muslim nations and the diversity of Islamic legal schools and theological streams (al‐Nasser ; Moosa ). As a result, the decrees issued by IOMS are highly influential in the health care and Islamic scholar communities.
The theme of the IOMS 8th annual Islamic medical seminar held in 1995 was “Some Medical Issues: An Islamic Perspective.” At the meeting, the use of ingredients traditionally considered juridically unclean or filthy, najis, in medicines was discussed by Islamic legists from the Fiqh Academy in Jeddah and Al‐Azhar University in Cairo in concert with medical experts from across the world. Representatives of Kuwait's Ministry of Health and the regional office of the WHO also participated in this meeting (Recommendations of the 8th Fiqh‐Medical Seminar ).
The seminar concluded by issuing a verdict with several recommendations. First, the legists reaffirmed a scholarly consensus, ijma', that the pig is juridically unclean, najas al‐ayn, and impermissible to consume. However, the scholars permitted the use of medicine with porcine components by referencing the Islamic ethico‐legal construct of transformation, istiḥāla. Their summary statement further noted that Muslim authorities should use animals that Muslims are permitted to eat as sources of medical gelatin (Recommendations of the 8th Fiqh‐Medical Seminar ).
At the IOMS 9th medical seminar in 1997 the use of porcine components in medicine was further clarified. In addition to those who participated in the 1995 meeting, representatives from the Islamic Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (ISESCO) also joined this meeting (Recommendations of the 9th ). The summary statement from this meeting explained that istiḥāla refers to the conversion of a forbidden substance into a different substance with different properties and characteristics than the original prohibited substance. Thus acetification, tanning, saponification, and other chemical reactions all were means for products to undergo istiḥāla. The scholars also offered another Islamic ethico‐legal argument to permit the use of porcine products in medicine: assimilation or istiḥlak. This Islamic ethico‐legal construct refers to the admixing of a negligible amount of a prohibited substance with a dominant permissible one resulting in the “obliteration” of the prohibited substance (Recommendations of the 9th ). Assimilation is evidenced by the newly created admixture demonstrating the properties of the dominant (permissible) substance. The scholars concluded that the use of pig enzymes in medicine is covered by istiḥlak and therefore resulting medicine is ḥalal (Recommendations of the 9th ). Thus Islamic scholars at the 9th IOMS seminar reaffirmed the permissibility of using porcine gelatin based on the Islamic ethico‐legal construct of istiḥāla, and further approved the use of pig enzymes in medicine production through the construct of istiḥlak.
In 2001, representatives of the WHO penned an official letter to address continuing Muslim concerns about the use of medicines that contain porcine components (Gezairy ). The letter excerpted the 1995 IOMS verdict and was circulated to many health policy stakeholders including vaccine manufacturers, physician groups, and the United Nations Children's Fund (UNICEF). The letter, and the excerpted verdict it contains, has been circulated widely and is used in policy‐relevant discourse by many different stakeholders. Illustratively, the Institute for Vaccine Safety uses the letter on their Web site to highlight the Islamic permissibility of vaccines with porcine components (Immunization Action Coalition ), and the WHO letter was similarly used to allay Muslim concerns over porcine‐based H1N1 vaccines in the United States by medical associations and vaccine manufacturers (Minnesota Medical Association ). Indeed, in personal email correspondence with medical information experts at Sanofi Pasteur and other vaccine companies, this author received copies of the WHO letter, and the pharmaceutical company representatives suggested that Islamic authorities approve of porcine components in vaccines without reservation (Thallmeyer ).
Part 2: The MUI and Porcine Vaccines
The MUI is a state‐sponsored religious council that issues fatawa on a wide range of issues with varying degrees of legal authority. With respect to foods and medicines, Indonesian law gives the MUI authority to determine whether or not products are ḥalal (TMO ). In 2008, the MUI issued a fatwa banning the use of a meningitis vaccine produced by GlaxoSmithKline citing the use of porcine products, specifically pig enzymes, during its manufacture (Jakarta Post ; Yessir ).
On the basis of this decision, the Health Ministry of Indonesia halted the distribution of the GSK meningitis vaccine (Yessir ), putting the Hajj journey of more than 200,000 Indonesian pilgrims at risk because meningitis vaccination is required prior to traveling for the Hajj. The decision was made all the more controversial because the Indonesian Health Ministry had already spent over $2 million on GSK vaccine prior to the MUI decree (Hossain ). Despite the costs associated with the decision, the Indonesian Health Minister insisted that only MUI‐certified ḥalal vaccines would be used in Indonesia. Cognizant of public pressure, and the religious needs of the Indonesian pilgrims, the MUI presented their religious concerns about the GSK vaccine to Saudi authorities. The Saudi authorities, however, denied an exemption from meningitis vaccination because of the high risk of transmission during pilgrimage and high rate of mortality from meningitis after transmission. Given the lack of an alternative vaccine and the Saudi reticence to grant an exemption, the MUI used the ethico‐legal concept of ḍarurah, extreme necessity, to permit first‐time Indonesian pilgrims to use the GSK vaccine (Sagita ; Jakarta Post ).
In 2010, however, the MUI issued another fatwa declaring two meningitis vaccines, one produced by the Swiss company Novartis and the other by China's Tian Yuan, to be free of porcine components and thus ḥalal (Hapsari ; Hossain ; Jakarta Post ). Implicitly, their ḍarurah‐based ruling permitting the use of porcine‐containing GSK vaccine was now revoked.
Up to this point, I have highlighted the principal Islamic ethico‐legal frames through which the IOMS and MUI issued their verdicts and recounted how these verdicts were used by health policy stakeholders—the WHO propagating the IOMS verdict through an official letter and the Indonesian Health Ministry procuring vaccines based on ḥalal approval from the MUI. In the next section, I will suggest that, from an applied Islamic bioethics vantage‐point, the way that the IOMS verdict was used by the WHO overlooks several critical features of Islamic ethico‐legal discourse that challenge the generalizability of the IOMS verdict. On the other hand, these same features were more appropriately taken into account by Indonesian health ministry officials when using the MUI verdict to inform health policy. I suggest that the proper application of juridical writings in health policy discourse requires a familiarity with Islamic ethico‐legal theory. Therefore my analysis highlights aspects of the ethico‐legal reasoning employed by the IOMS and MUI verdicts only to illustrate larger concepts within Islamic ethico‐legal theory that need to be taken into account when using verdicts to inform health policy.
Recounting the Narrative through the Lens of Applied Islamic Bioethics
As we turn to examining the IOMS and MUI verdicts more closely, defining a few concepts will aid the reader in placing this study within Islamic bioethics scholarship.
The study of fatawa (singular fatwa) and qararat (singular qarar) represents the cornerstone of Islamic bioethics research. Fatawa and qararat play a role similar to that of legal response literature in Halakhaic reasoning, and are nonbinding ethico‐legal opinions of traditional Islamic jurisconsults and juridical councils. These judgments utilize a method of religious‐text prioritization and ethico‐legal argument that is mapped out in Islamic moral theology and jurisprudential theory, usul al‐fiqh. Fatawa and qararat are used ubiquitously by the laity (Muslim patients and physicians) to guide health‐care behaviors, by Islamic bioethics researchers to derive normative goals for medical practice, by policy actors to craft regulations and law, and by religious leaders to advise their communities on ethical challenges in health care. Fatawa and qararat, as expressions of the Islamic ethico‐legal tradition, further represent a window into the jurisconsult's mind as he/she approaches modern medicine and are central to applied Islamic bioethics scholarship. Applied Islamic bioethics is a discipline that seeks to (1) examine the ways in which Islamic authorities approach ethical questions raised by Muslim health‐care providers, religious leaders, and patients in their dealings with medicine and biotechnology and to (2) study the application of religious verdicts by health‐care providers, patients, and health‐care stakeholders. Thus the field is founded upon the study of fatawa and qararat.
With this introduction I argue that a neglect of three concepts contributes to the possible misreading of the IOMS verdict. The first concept is the distinction between a fatwa and a ḥukm. I contest that the IOMS and MUI verdicts are morally and legally nonequivalent on the basis of this distinction. The second concept is that schools of Islamic law differ in their acceptance of ethico‐legal constructs. Therefore verdicts using ethico‐legal reasoning based on a particular school of law may be considered deficient according to other schools of law. I will use the construct of istiḥāla to elaborate upon this idea. The last concept relates to the differentiation between a normative and a contingent ruling. This notion will be illustrated by examining how the verdicts cite ḍarurah, extreme necessity.
A Fatwa vis‐à‐vis a ḥukm
The fact that the IOMS and MUI religious decrees differ illustrates the pluralistic and nonauthoritarian nature of Islamic ethico‐legal discourse. Classical Sunni Islamic theology maintains the absence of a divinely inspired religious class that is a privileged authority on religious matters. Instead, Sunni Islamic ethico‐legal reasoning is marked by an adherence to a more‐or‐less agreed‐upon epistemological framework for moral assessment and an accompanying deductive method termed usul al‐fiqh. This science is enshrined within the moral theology and legal theories of the four Sunni schools of law, Maliki, Hanafi, Shafi, and Hanbali, and is practiced by trained jurisconsults. Islamic scholars who carry traditional licenses (ijazat) to issue fatawa consequently are moral authorities. These fatawa are nonbinding and considered morally equivalent approximations of the transcendent Divine rule, ḥukm Allah. It follows then, that individuals and institutions are free to choose among the extant fatawa based on their own assessment of the rigor of argument and the moral authority of the jurisconsult(s). Importantly, the fatwa of an individual Islamic jurisconsult and that of a juridical council are both nonbinding and legally equivalent.
The word ḥukm describes several different concepts in the Islamic ethico‐legal tradition and its ubiquitous usage can be confusing to the nonspecialist. In a literal sense, ḥukm signifies a rule, a judgment, or a law. According to usul al‐fiqh, a ḥukm represents a Divine communication about the moral boundaries of human action, hence it is a transcendental norm: the eternal rule of God (Moosa ; Nyazee ). This “beforetime” Divine judgment is “discovered” within the temporal realm through empirical indicators, adilla, which are themselves discerned through the use of usul al‐fiqh methodology. While the “transcendent ḥukm is always at an ontological remove” the empirical rule finding activity of the jurist yields an approximate ruling also referred to as a ḥukm (Moosa , 19).
Specifically, the end result of usul al‐fiqh deliberations are classified as al‐ḥukm al‐wadi or al‐ḥukm al‐taklifi. Al‐ḥukm al‐wadi enacts a cause, condition, or hindrance to some action. For example, a Qur'anic verse may detail the categories of people who are required to fast and those who are exempted. Al‐ḥukm al‐takleefi, on the other hand, is an assessment that locates an action along an ethical gradient from obligatory to perform to obligatory to refrain from, each gradient having its own afterlife ramifications (Kamali ; Nyazee ).
Moving from moral theology to the world of political authority brings forth an added classification for ḥukm, ḥukm al‐qadi. In this article my use of the term ḥukm signifies this particular type of ḥukm. A ḥukm al‐qadi is simply a law issued by a Muslim state authority. According to Sunni legal theory a Muslim living under an Islamic state authority (here I use the term Islamic to note that the political state must use the Shar'iah as a source of law although the exact nature of how is a point of controversy) is liable for following the law of the land, the ḥukm al‐qadi, in so far as it does not contradict a religious obligation that is universally agreed upon and of a higher priority to be fulfilled (Nyazee ). For example, a Muslim ruler may legislate that polygamy is not permitted in his kingdom. A Muslim living under the protection of this ruler is liable for following this law, even though the legislation restricts the range of what is permissible (polygamy) within Islamic law. If the Muslim were not to obey this law he would be morally and legally liable; that is, he would be both sinning and be at risk for legal sanction.
Returning to the matter at hand a fatwa is transformed into a ḥukm al qadi by means of state backing. This state authority, a ruler or hakim, in turn shoulders the moral responsibility for governance over Muslims (wilaya). According to the majority of Sunni legal theorists, a ḥukm can only issue forth from a Muslim state authority, hakim, as non‐Muslim rulers do not bear the moral and ethico‐legal responsibility for Muslim communities (Arozullah and Kholwadia ). The transformation of a fatwa to a ḥukm is morally and legally significant. At the level of a fatwa the Muslim is allowed to consult other fatawa in his quest for guidance and the “best” approximation of God's rule. However, when a Muslim state authority adopts a fatwa and turns it into a ḥukm al‐qadi as the law of the land, Muslims are both morally and legally bound to follow that judgment. In effect, the one among many options represented by a fatwa turns into a singular binding judgment as a ḥukm.
From this discussion it follows then that the Islamic jurist or juridical body's relationship to a Muslim state authority determines the moral and legal significance attached to their verdict. The nature of the relationship between the state and religious authority has been a subject of intense debate in both medieval and modern Islam. These debates involve theology and political theory, and predominately revolve around the questions: What is the role of Divine Law (Shar'iah) in regulating human conduct? and, In what ways should the moral and ethical authority of religious scholars enter into the legal and public policy domains? Differences in Mutalizite, Ashari’, and Maturidi scholastic theology (kalam) as well as in Sunni and Shiite moral theology and jurisprudential theory (usul al‐fiqh) can be traced to differences in views about the relationship between political and religious authority. Differing views also led to armed struggles during the Islamic caliphate such as the Khawariji battles and the Mu'tazilate Inquisition (Miḥna), and answers to these questions inform the ideologies of Islamic movements such as the Hizb‐ut‐Tehrir, the Ikhwan al‐Muslimeen, Wahhabism, and al‐Qaeda. While delving into these debates is beyond the scope of this article, it suffices to note that the Sunni orthopraxy has maintained a separation between religious authority and political authority and thus legal opinions (fatwa) are not automatically judicial decisions (ḥukm).
As far as the MUI verdict is concerned, it represents a ḥukm al qadi for Muslims in Indonesia. Since Indonesian law delegates the authority to determine what foodstuffs are considered ḥalal to the MUI, their legal opinion becomes elevated from fatwa status to that of being a ḥukm. This transformation explains why the Indonesian Health Ministry felt obliged to act in accordance to the MUI's ruling.
On the other hand, while the IOMS fatwa represents the opinion of a group of premier Islamic jurisconsults, it carries the same ethico‐legal authority as the opinion of any other juridical council, or even one jurisconsult. Thus while the IOMS decree may influence health behaviors of Muslims around the globe, it remains only one of the many fatwa an individual Muslim, or a Muslim state actor, may choose to follow. If a state authority were to adopt the IOMS decree as law of the land then the verdict would correspond to a morally and legally binding ḥukm al‐qadi within that state authority's jurisdiction.
Unwittingly, the WHO letter, along with the IOMS verdict it excerpts, has been repeatedly used by health policy actors in the West as a “final word” decree, betraying the nonbinding and one‐option‐among‐many character of the judgment. This misinterpretation is understandable, given that the letter lacks any mention of differing opinions by Islamic juridical authorities, and does not contain a caveat that, the IOMS verdict is a nonbinding opinion. Thus health policy actors, such as the vaccine manufacturers, seem to have construed the WHO cover letter language addressed to “all the health ministries” in order to relieve the “burden of all Muslims (abna al ummah)” (Gezairy ) as signifying that the verdict is globally applicable to Muslims living in Muslim majority nations as well as in the diaspora. Yet, for Muslims living in a minority status without political governance the IOMS fatwa cannot be treated as a binding ḥukm al qadi.
Istiḥāla, Complete Transformation, across the Sunni Schools of Law
When reading fatawa, it is critical to note the ethico‐legal constructs employed by jurisconsults when making their argument. The constructs used by legists adherent to one school of law may not be considered valid by legists belonging to another school of law. Thus a particular verdict may not have resonance across schools and its generalizability is challenged. This feature within Islamic ethico‐legal theory is illustrated in the IOMS's reliance upon istiḥāla to deem porcine‐based medicines permissible.
What exactly istiḥāla signifies physically and how the construct should be used in ethico‐legal assessment is a matter of continuing debate within the Sunni legal schools. Generally defined as tabdeel al‐maḥiyyat or tabdeel al‐ḥal, istiḥāla signifies “(the) chang(e) in nature of (a)…substance to produce a different substance in name, properties and characteristics” (Recommendations of the 9th ). Looking to the natural world and at Prophetic examples, classical Islamic jurists noted that while the Qur'an and the Prophet prohibited drinking wine, the consumption of vinegar was allowed (al‐Naisaburi , 23:5091). The same type of circumstances and judgments surrounded the use of the tanned hides of dead animals. These paradigmatic examples, where an Islamically unclean (najis) substance underwent a change in character such that the resulting substance was considered clean and permissible to use, informed the techno‐scientific imagination of the medieval jurists such that the construct of complete transformation, istiḥāla, came into the vocabulary of Islamic law. Technically, then, istiḥāla signifies the transmutation of a ḥaram material into a ḥalal substance. As noted above, the IOMS decrees invoke istiḥāla to deem porcine‐based vaccines permissible.
From an applied Islamic bioethics viewpoint the problem lies not in the verdict's ethico‐legal reasoning; rather, it is that there is no mention in the final verdict, and perhaps thereby in the synopsis disseminated by the WHO, that the Sunni schools of law disagree on whether istiḥāla applies to porcine products. Thus stakeholders who try to use the fatwa to inform health policy may mistakenly construe a false consensus of opinion and believe that the fatwa is universally acceptable.
In reality there is a considerable degree of variance within and across the Sunni legal schools as to whether istiḥāla applies to products of pig origin. Briefly, the prevailing opinion in the Hanafi school (al‐Hattab , 1:97; Ibn Nujaym , 1:294) and Maliki school (al‐Dusuqi , 1:97; al‐Hattab , 1:97) is that istiḥāla can purify pig products. However, the Shafi doctrine is that porcine products do not fall under the purview of istiḥāla (al‐Shirbini , 1:236). The dominant opinion in the Hanbali school is debatable, with the majority view being that istiḥāla does not purify pig (al‐Dusuqi , 1:97; al‐Buhuti , 1:214–15; Ibn Qudamah , 1:86, 2:66), however one opinion of Imam Ahmad (Ibn Qudamah , 1:76), and the opinion of Ibn Taymiyyah and Ibn Qayyim al‐Jawziyyah is that porcine products are covered by istiḥāla (Ibn Qayyim al‐Jawziyyah , 2:15; Ibn Taymiyyah n.d., 21:70). It is important to note that there are minority opinions within the Hanafi school, like that traced to Imam Abu Yusuf (Ibn Humam , 1:202) that discount istiḥāla for porcine. While the IOMS juridical council (or any jurisconsult) is free to judge based on the opinion of another school, an istiḥāla‐based argument is by no means universally acceptable.
To reiterate my point, it is critical for policy stakeholders to recognize the inherent limitations of a particular fatwa when using it as the basis for health policy. One such limitation may stem from the usage of ethico‐legal constructs that are deemed valid by some schools of law and invalid by others. To accurately assess the acceptability of a particular fatwa within a community, policy stakeholders must therefore be aware of the ethico‐legal proclivities of a specific Muslim community, and be cognizant of whether contested constructs are employed within the ethico‐legal reasoning of a particular fatwa.
The IOMS verdict's universal appeal is challenged by its reliance on istiḥāla. Given this limitation, the WHO's suggestion that the verdict would “relieve all Muslims” (Gezairy ) may be an overstatement of its potential relevance within the global Muslim community. Moving to the MUI, their fatwa declared the GSK vaccine ḥaram due to porcine components used in its production. This ruling may, in part, be explained by the fact that most Indonesian jurisconsults incline toward the doctrinal Shafi position that istiḥāla does not apply to porcine. A detailed analysis of their fatwa would provide greater clarity on the ethico‐legal arguments they employ to argue for the ḥaram status of the vaccine. However, this type of analysis is unnecessary to make the point that the MUI was free to offer their own verdict even while the IOMS was being circulated because the IOMS has no legal authority over Indonesian Muslims.
Ḍarurah‐Based Rulings: Considering Normative Assessments in the Islamic Ethico‐Legal Tradition
Another critical concept that may be overlooked by stakeholders in seeking to apply Islamic verdicts is the difference between a normative and a contingent ruling. This element of Islamic ethico‐legal deliberation may not be readily noticed by nonlegal specialists, and as a result, a ruling with a limited scope may be seen as more widely applicable. As a rule of thumb whenever a verdict cites ḍarurah as the basis for judgment, the resulting ethico‐legal opinion is nonnormative.
Technically ḍarurah is an Islamic ethico‐legal concept that describes circumstances of extreme necessity. Its usage in Islamic ethico‐legal argumentation is captured by the legal maxim, al‐darurat tubih al‐mahzurat—extreme necessity renders the impermissible to be permissible. This maxim is derived from several Qur'anic verses and Prophetic statements that indicate extreme circumstances may require normative prohibitions to be overturned. A verse that is of particular relevance to this discussion reads:
Say (O Prophet): I find not in that which is revealed unto me aught prohibited to an eater that he eat thereof, except it be carrion, or blood poured forth, or swine‐flesh for that verily is foul or the abomination which was immolated to the name of other than Allah. But whoso is compelled (thereto), neither craving nor transgressing, (for him) Lo! your Lord is Forgiving, Merciful. ([al‐An'am:145] Pickthall )
Even while forbidding the consumption of pig, the verse puts forth an exception noting that “whoso is compelled” may partake of the forbidden food.
Another related legal maxim states al‐mushaqqa tajlabu al‐tayseer, that hardship allows for bringing about ease (Ibn Nujaym , 64). Particularizing these principles, the four Sunni schools of law allow an extreme necessity, ḍarurah, to overturn a normative prohibition when a core objective of the Islamic ethico‐legal code is at stake. These core objectives, maqaṣid, of the Islamic ethico‐legal code are the protection of religion, life, intellect, lineage, and property (Auda ; Padela ). Defining what constitutes an extreme necessity is controversial and can vary from Islamic jurisconsult to jurisconsult, and from legal school to school. Circumstances that lead to invoking a ḍarurah are, by definition, motivating the exception and thus the judgment represents a nonideal scenario. In Islamic bioethics, ḍarurah is invoked with considerable variance and ambiguity.
The IOMS verdict does not rely on ḍarurah; rather, it considers istiḥāla as the operative construct allowing the use of porcine‐based medicines. One may, therefore, conclude that the IOMS judgment is a normative assessment. However, the legists offer a caveat limiting the scope of their permissive ruling by stating that “(we) recommends (sic) the necessity of utilizing skins and bones of (ḥalal) animals for the purpose of extracting gelatin…as this will…avoid sources that might be juridically unacceptable” (Recommendations of the 8th ). It appears, then, that using a vaccine comprised of porcine gelatin seems to be less than ideal and that nonporcine gelatin is the preferred norm.
The MUI initially declared the GSK porcine‐based vaccine to be ḥaram but subsequently permitted its usage by citing ḍarurah. For these scholars, the conditions that came together to meet the threshold of ḍarurah were the lack of a nonporcine alternative and the Saudi mandate of meningitis vaccination prior to Hajj.
Noting the normative or contingent nature of a ruling is integral to appropriately applying the fatwa. Accordingly if the approval of porcine‐based medications is based on several contingencies, then it follows that the verdict is actionable only for as long as those particular circumstances remain in effect. In the health policy realm, a further implication arises: the conditions that create the social circumstances that necessitate a contingent ruling are themselves intervention points. In other words, when a ruling is motivated by circumstances that constitute ḍarurah, health policy stakeholders may work to change the contexts that impede a more normative ruling.
Although the final IOMS verdict is not motivated by ḍarurah the text suggests that using porcine gelatin is not ideal. This qualification seems to have been overlooked by vaccine industry stakeholders as they promote the “Islamic” sanction of their porcine‐based vaccines (Padela ). For example, a medical information specialist with Sanofi Pasteur stated that their porcine‐based vaccines have been approved by Islamic authorities and referenced the WHO letter (Thallmeyer ). Furthermore, interpreting the ruling as normative allowed the industry to consider the status quo as acceptable to the Muslim world.
The 2008 MUI verdict changed this evaluation in that declaring porcine‐based vaccines ḥaram created the market‐based impetus to create meningitis vaccines that were porcine‐free. Even though the MUI allowed for the use of porcine‐based vaccines by means of ḍarurah, it was clearer to health policy stakeholders that this permission was conditional. Both verdicts had tangible impact upon the vaccine industry.
Final Remarks
In this article I examined how health policy stakeholders utilized the IOMS and MUI verdicts on the permissibility of using vaccines. I highlighted aspects of the arguments employed in these verdicts to point out key concepts within the Islamic ethico‐legal tradition that need to be taken into account when using Islamic verdicts to inform health policy. Specifically, I commented on (1) the distinction between a fatwa and a ḥukm, (2) the nonuniversal acceptance of Islamic ethico‐legal constructs across the schools of law, and (3) the differentiation between a normative and a conditional ruling. In conclusion, I offer several recommendations for the producers and consumers of Islamic bioethical discourse that will facilitate products that better meet the needs of Muslim patients, physicians, religious leaders, and policy stakeholders.
First, I recommend that Islamic jurisconsults (1) clearly note the validity of the particular ethico‐legal constructs employed in their verdicts across the Islamic schools of law, (2) unambiguously delineate the circumstances their decrees address, and (3) specify conditions under which the ruling is operable. In the past, individuals and state actors often sought fatawa from local Islamic authorities. This “neighborhood” fatwa meant that the issuing Islamic authority was well known and trusted by the seeker of the fatwa, and that the fatwa was communicated through the medium of a jurist who could explain the ethico‐legal rationale behind it, and the conditions under which action was due upon a fatwa.
In the era of mass media, global interconnectedness, and with the advent of the Internet, Islamic verdicts are now part of a global public discourse. The increased number of options presented by the myriad of extant fatawa allows the seeker to select and act upon the fatwa that most clearly suits his or her circumstances, and is viewed as the most accurate description of the Divine law. At the same time, however, the increased proliferation of fatawa creates the scenario where those seeking to implement a fatwa may be far removed from the Islamic scholars who issue them. The “transnational” fatwa opens up the door for misappropriation and misunderstanding as the verdict comes to be decoupled from context, and removed from the interpretative medium of a trained Islamic jurist. Therefore clearly delineating the circumstances a particular fatwa addresses, and the conditions under which the fatwa is actionable, will make it easier to identify whether a specific verdict is transferable across time, space, and context. Moreover, by clarifying whether the ethico‐legal constructs employed by a jurist are universally acceptable across the Islamic schools of law would facilitate the critical evaluation and successive refinements of the fatwa. In this way, Islamic bioethical discourse can adapt to better meet the changing needs of the Muslim community while at the same time maintaining fidelity to the ethico‐legal tradition.
Additionally, I believe that Islamic juridical authorities must consider the policy implications of their verdicts. I do not mean to suggest that jurists do not routinely take into account the social realities impacting their ethico‐legal deliberations; however, I suggest that policy‐level ramifications may need to be more central to the deliberative processes. As fatawa participate in a global Islamic bioethics discourse, and transnational health policy stakeholders disseminate and use Islamic rulings, anticipating the downstream policy (mis)application beforehand may impact the content of the ruling, as well as compel jurists to be more lucid in the writing of the final verdict.
To more fully consider the ways potential rulings would be used in the public policy realm, a multidisciplinary engagement is needed within Islamic juridical councils. Fiqh academies tend to predominately involve medical experts and Islamic jurists, yet Islamic theologians, health policy experts, social scientists, patients, and others may all serve as content‐experts in bioethical deliberation. By bringing into dialogue these oft‐overlooked experts, juridical councils can spawn an “Islamic” bioethics whose practitioners are literate in both the Islamic sources (the texts) and the social realities (the contexts), and effect a discourse that represents a living tradition engaging with the complex bioethical challenges of modern times.
Acknowledgments
This article grew out of a presentation at the conference on “Islamic Bioethics: The Interplay of Islam and the West” that was held in Doha, Qatar, June 24–25, 2012. This conference was part of the project “Islamic Medical and Scientific Ethics (IMSE),” funded by the Qatar National Research Fund (QNRF) and organized by the Library of the School of Foreign Service in Qatar (SFSQ), Georgetown University in cooperation with the Bioethics Research Library, Georgetown University, Washington, DC. The article was also presented in partial form at the conference on “Health‐Related Issues and Islamic Normativity” at the University of Hamburg, Germany in June 2012. We thank Shaykh Amin Kholwadia, Prof. Ebrahim Moosa, and Shaykh Musa Furber for their insightful research, discussions, and encouragement that led to this article. We also note the assistance of Mufti Zubair Butt and Mufti Ehzaz for assistance with citations. The research leading to this manuscript was, in part, funded through the Robert Wood Johnson Foundation Clinical Scholars Program, and carried out as Visiting Fellow at the Oxford Centre for Islamic Studies.
References
Arozullah, Ahsan, and Mohammed AminKholwadia. 2013. “Wilayah (Authority and Governance) and its Implications for Islamic Bioethics: A Sunni Maturidi Perspective.” Journal of Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34:95–104.
Auda, Jasser. 2008. Maqaṣid Al‐Shariah as Philosophy of Islamic Law: A Systems Approach. Herndon, VA: International Institute of Islamic Thought.
Buhuti, Mansur ibn Yunus al‐. 1974. Kashshaf Al‐Qina'an Matn Al‐Iqna’. Mecca: Matba'h Al‐Hukumah.
Dusuqi, Muhammad bin Ahmad ibn ‘Arafah al‐. 1996. Hashiyat Al‐Dusuqi. Beirut: Dar al‐Kutub al‐Ilmiyyah.
Gezairy, Hussein A.2001. The Use of Unlawful or Juridically Unclean Substances in Food and Medicine. Alexandria, Egypt: World Health Organization Regional Office for the Eastern Mediterranean.
Hapsari, Arghea D.2010. “MUI Dismisses Experts’ Claim on Vaccine, Defends Fatwa.” Jakarta Post , August 9. http://www.thejakartapost.com/news/2010/08/09/mui‐dismisses‐experts%E2%80%99‐claim‐vaccine‐defends‐fatwa.html
Hattab, Abu ‘Abdullah Muhammad bin ‘Abd al‐Rahman al‐. 1995. Mawahib al‐Jalil. Beirut: Dar Al‐Kutub Al‐’Ilmiyyah.
Hossain, Sazzad. 2012. “Halal Vaccine for Hajis.” The Financial Express . 20:323. http://www.thefinancialexpressbd.com/more.php?news_id=126592&date=2012–04–13
Ibn Humam, Kamal al‐Din Muhammad. 1995. Sharh Fath al‐Qadir. Beirut: Dar Al‐Kutub.
Ibn Nujaym, Zayn al‐Din. 1983. Al‐Bahr Al‐Ra'iq: Sharh Kanz al‐Daqa ‘iq. 8 vols. Quetta, Pakistan: al‐Maktabah al‐Majidiyah.
Ibn Nujaym, Zayn al‐Din. 1993. “Al‐Qai'dah Al‐Rabi'ah: Al‐Mashaqah Tajlib al‐Taysir .” In al‐Ashbah wa al‐Nazha'ir. Beirut: Dar Al‐Katub Al‐'Ilmiyyah.
Ibn Qayyimal‐Jawziyyah, Shams al‐Din Abu ‘Abdullah Muhammad bin Abi Bakr. 1993. ‘Alam Al‐Muwaqqi'in ‘an Rabb Al‐’Alamin. Cairo: Dar Al‐Hadith.
Ibn Qudamah, Abu Muhammad ‘Abdullah bin Ahmad bin Muhammad. 1994. al‐Mughni. Beirut: Dar Al‐Kutub Al‐’Ilmiyyah.
Ibn Taymiyyah, Abu al‐’Abbas Taqi al‐Din. n.d. Majmu'ah al‐Fatawa. Al‐Ribat: Maktabat al‐Ma'arif. 21:70.
Immunization Action Coalition. 2003. Religious Leaders Approval of Use of Vaccines Containing Porcine Gelatin. Issue brief no. 400. July 21, 2003. http://www.immunize.org/genr.d/issue400.htm#n8
Jakarta Post. 2010a. “Govt Set to Distribute Halal Meningitis Vaccine to Pilgrims .” July 31, 2010. http://www.thejakartapost.com/news/2010/07/31/govt‐setdistribute‐%E1%B8%A5alal‐meningitis‐vaccine‐pilgrims.html
Jakarta Post. 2010b. “More Scientists Question Halal Vaccines.” Jakarta Post . August 28. http://www.thejakartapost.com/news/2010/08/28/morescientists‐question‐%E1%B8%A5alal‐vaccines.html
Kamali, Mohammad H.2003. Principles of Islamic Jurisprudence. Cambridge: Islamic Texts Society.
Minnesota Medical Association. “MMA Urges H1N1 Vaccination for Children of All Faiths .” News release, October 28, 2009. http://www.mnmed.org/News/NewsFullStory/tabid/2266/ArticleID/3412/CBModuleId/4456/default.aspx.
Moosa, Ebrahim. 1998. “Allegory of the Rule (ḥukm): Law as Simulacrum in Islam?” History of Religions 38:1–24.
Moosa, Ebrahim. 1999. “Languages of Change in Islamic Law: Redefining Death in Modernity.” Islamic Studies 38:305–42.
Naisaburi, Abul‐Hussain ‘Asakiruddin Muslim bin Hajjaj al‐Qushairi al‐. 1972. Sahih Muslim. Translated by Abdul H.Siddiqui, 4 volumes. Lahore, Pakistan: Sh. Muhammad Ashraf.
Nasser, Lahem al‐.2009. “The Islamic Fiqh Academy .” Asharq Alawsat Newspaper. http://www.asharq‐e.com/news.asp?id=17140
Nyazee, Imran A. K.2005. Theories of Islamic Law: The Methodology of Ijtihad. Islamabad, Pakistan: Islamic Research Institute Press.
Padela, Aasim I.2007. “Islamic Medical Ethics: A Primer.” Bioethics 21:169–78.
Padela, Aasim I.2010. “Public Health Measures and Individualized Decision‐Making: The Confluence of H1N1 Vaccine, and Islamic Bioethics.” Human Vaccines 6:754–56.
Picktḥall, Mohammed M.2005. “The Meaning of the Glorious Qur'an .” http://www.sacred‐texts.com/isl/pick/index.htm
Recommendations of the 8th Fiqh‐Medical Seminar. 1995. Report. www.islamset.com/bioethics/8thfiqh.html
Recommendations of the 9th Fiqh‐Medical Seminar. 1997. Report. www.islamset.com/bioethics/9thfiqh.html
Sagita, Dessy. 2009. “Vaccine OK in ‘Cases of Emergency.’” Jakarta Globe . July 24, 2009. http://www.thejakartaglobe.com/home/meningitis‐vaccine‐ok‐for‐first‐hajj‐mui/319729
Shirbini, Shamsal‐Din Muhammad bin Muhammad al‐Khatib al‐. 1994. Mughni al‐Muhtaj. Beirut: Dar Al‐Kutub Al‐’Ilmiyyah.
Thallmayer, Jeanne. 2012. E‐mail to Dr. Benjamin Brielmaier , October 2.
TMO. 2009. “Indonesia Minister, Clerics Clash over Hajj Swine Vaccine Requirement.” The Muslim Observer 11:11–16. http://muslimmedianetwork.com/mmn/?tag=meningitis‐vaccine
Yessir. 2010. “Indonesia – MUI Issued Fatwa Banning GSK Meningitis Vaccine .” A Big Message for an Upside Down World. http://www.abigmessage.com/indonesia‐mui‐issued‐fatwa‐banning‐gsk‐meningitis‐vaccine.html