When the late nineteenth‐century authors John William Draper (1811–1882) and Andrew Dickson White (1832–1918) construed their thesis of a fundamental, age‐old conflict between religion and science they could be certain to appeal to contemporary sensibilities shared by many readers not only in the Anglo‐American world but also on the European continent. In Europe, Protestant resentment of alleged Catholic antimodernism had reached new heights following the First Vatican Council's proclamation of papal infallibility in 1870.
Peter Harrison rightly rejects these and other mythical interpretations of the history of science. For a historian of early modern Europe, such as myself, he is “running in open doors,” but he is undoubtedly correct in reminding us that such fundamentally erroneous notions are still en vogue in some quarters (Harrison [2006] 2011a, 118; , 24, 51f., 172).
THE ALLEGORICAL READING OF THE BOOK OF NATURE
Harrison finds himself in agreement with most salient research of the last decades in highlighting the seventeenth century, particularly in England, as a landmark in terms of redefining the relationship of religion and science, conveying to it a form that was to last (in England) until the first half of the nineteenth century. One important aspect, which was to feed into the physico‐theological movement in the course of the second half of the century, was the increasing emphasis on the usefulness of science, understood in anthropocentric terms. This went hand in hand with the popularization of the Baconian motif of the possibility of human dominion over nature (Harrison , 126, 138–40f.). In other words, it became possible to conceive of progress, specifically as something “arising out of the cumulative contributions of numerous individuals to a body of knowledge” (Harrison , 119). Harrison argues that the establishment of transpersonal, collective bodies of doctrine in the wake of the Reformation paved the way for this new definition of scientia and religio (Harrison , 11, 16, 93). However, as the following will show, I doubt whether that which undoubtedly applies to the new role of religion is likewise applicable in a comparable way to science.
Elsewhere, Harrison has pointed out that the sixteenth‐century reformers consciously opted for the literal or historical sense in interpreting the Bible, thus rejecting allegorical interpretation, and, more generally, the medieval conception of the fourfold meaning of biblical texts (Harrison , passim; Harrison [] 2011b, 198, 204). This allowed for a new approach to the Book of Nature. I do not question that a literal or historical reading of the book of Genesis, in particular, may have had “a major impact on the development of experimental science in seventeenth‐century England” (Harrison [] 2011b, 210). It is nonetheless possible that the Reformation did not represent the kind of exegetical caesura suggested by Harrison (Van der Meer and Oosterhoff ). However, assuming that it did, I question the linearity of the “disenchantment of the world”—a notion evidently borrowed from Max Weber—which is invoked to buttress “the admittedly risky proposition that modern science, and indeed modernity in general, is in some way deeply indebted to Protestantism” (Harrison [] 2011b, 211).
In the Fall of Man and the Foundations of Science, Peter Harrison argued that in seventeenth‐century science “it is experimental philosophy that is most indebted to Calvinist ideas of human nature. Here we encounter a critical scrutiny of human faculties along with frank appraisals of their inherent limitations. … [that] the commitment to the pursuit of knowledge would be partial and probable, that it would be attained only after much drudgery and labor, and that it would require the coordinated efforts of many individuals” (Harrison , 249). However, we should by no means overlook the deeply ambivalent role of Calvinism, or better, Reformed theology, in seventeenth‐century science. The Dutch Calvinist neo‐scholastics such as Gisbert Voetius (1589–1676) and his adherents, made every effort to stop the spread of Cartesianism within Dutch learned culture, and while doing so, they claimed to be the true torchbearers of original Genevan Calvinism (Vermij , 239–331). This spilled over into the Reformed camp in Switzerland, where resistance against Cartesianism reached its climax with the Reformed churches’ Formula Consensus of 1675 that even declared the diacritical signs in biblical Hebrew texts to be divinely inspired. Here, the literal interpretation of the Bible turned into a boomerang against the promotion of the new science. The Reformed authorities of Zürich reprimanded Johann Jakob Scheuchzer as late as 1721 for his public backing of Copernicanism (Nagel and Gehr , 194f.). All this was not in keeping with the alleged disenchantment of the world initiated by the Reformation.
The relatively cautious connection established between the reformers’ rejection of the fourfold meaning of biblical texts in favor of a literal or historical reading and the rise of the new science in the course of the seventeenth century in The Territories of Science and Religion is the main theme of Harrison's The Bible, Protestantism, and the Rise of Natural Science of 1998. Here, the author acknowledges the discussions of the Weber‐Tawney approach to the socioeconomic role of early modern Calvinism and, in particular, the extension of this approach into the history of seventeenth‐century science by Robert Merton ([] 1978) and Charles Webster (Webster ). Given the ambivalent result of these debates, he insists that neither Calvinism nor Puritanism provide the specific background for his study and that, as a result, he intends to focus more generally on the impact that the sixteenth‐century reformers’ insistence on the literal interpretation of scripture had on the relationship between Protestantism and science. In spite of his declared distance to the arguments proferred by Weber and Tawney, his main argument here, as well as in his last monograph of 2015, is very much part of a Weberian view of the “disenchantment of the world” in the wake of the Reformation. Weber's larger and more lasting concern, of which “The Protestant Ethic” was just one component, was the unstoppable rationalization of the Western world which filled him, on the one hand, with admiration, on the other, with an almost dystopian concern (Schluchter , ).
Peter Harrison has made it clear that he does not wish “to be seen as setting out a monocausal thesis for the rise of modern science, for there is no reason why a range of factors should not play the same role,” yet he insists that “the literalist mentality initiated by the Protestant reformers, and sponsored by their successors” was “the most significant” of these factors (Harrison , 8). The Territories of Science and Religion keeps endorsing this view. In what follows, I want to question Harrison's hierarchical ranking of the factors in question (for some preliminaries cf. von Greyerz ).
John Hedley Brooke's important Science and Religion provides a good illustration of the intimate connection between the new “literalist mentality” of the reformers and the Weberian conception of the disenchantment of the world. Much like Harrison after him, he argues that the reformers’ emphasis on the literal reading of the Bible could “assist in the disenchantment of nature” (Brooke , 71). He refers to Thomas Erastus's (1523–1583) criticism of judicial astrology based on a close literal reading of the first chapter of Genesis and argues that “the refusal of Erastus to derive the forms of bodies [on earth—KvG] from the stars, or from anything within nature, pointed toward the empiricism of Bacon, for whom the only guides to knowledge were experience and the Bible” (Brooke , 71). However, his choice of a witness is, in a sense, indicative of the problems of continuity inherent in the disenchantment thesis, and this for two reasons. First, the most severe criticism of judicial astrology was voiced before the Reformation by Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463–1494). In his recent monumental history of Copernicanism, Robert Westman shows how Pico's misgivings kept inspiring similar criticism all through the sixteenth century (Westman ; , 115–22). As far as the German Reformation is concerned, we should be aware that, among the two most prominent Wittenberg reformers, it was Philipp Melanchthon, who, unlike Luther, showed a keen interest in natural philosophy generally, and in astrological predictions in particular (Caroti ; Kusukawa , passim).
Second, while questioning the raison d’être of judicial astrology, Erastus was at the same time very much involved in the contemporary controversy about how to deal with witches. Although Erastus spiritualized witchcraft as something which happened in the witches’ thoughts rather than in real action, just like Johann Weyer, whom he fought bitterly, he nonetheless called for their execution on account of their apostasy (Gunnoe , 352–58; von Greyerz , 125–27). No sign of disenchantment here. In fact, as Stuart Clark has shown, the majority of the sixteenth‐ and seventeenth‐century authors of demonologies had an evangelical‐clerical background (Clark , 437–56; Walsham , 25–28). The dénouement of many of these complexities, which make it difficult to look at the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries in terms of the disenchantment of the world, took place during the last decades of the seventeenth and the early eighteenth century. This is when the educated classes lost their interest in astrological prediction (Capp , 190, 276–81; Curry , 45–91; von Greyerz ), as well as in the persecution of witches (Sharpe , 211–302), and when the movement of physico‐theology got off the ground.
All this goes to show that implicitly wedding the reformers’ insistence on a literal reading of Holy Scripture and the Book of Nature with the notion of the disenchantment of the world must inevitably result in a mésalliance. By insisting that an allegorical reading of the Book of Nature was henceforth on the way out, this view implicitly adopts a teleology which ultimately fails to do justice to the complexity of the development of seventeenth‐century science. For there is an important tradition of scientific reasoning which clearly does not fit the concept of the disenchantment of the world. It is the alchemical tradition which perpetuates an allegorical reading of the book of nature all the way down to the end of the seventeenth century, when Isaac Newton moved from Cambridge to London, where he became Master of the Mint, and consequently gave up his laboratory (Westfall , 332; Golinski ). There is no need to rehearse the difficulties that the research into this tradition had to overcome before it got integrated into the mainstream narrative of the Scientific Revolution. It is well known by now that the majority of the unpublished papers left by Newton deal with alchemical questions (Dobbs , 235–48).
That a similar case can be made for Boyle is perhaps still less established. Few Boyle specialists would still call Boyle “the father of modern chemistry” (Harrison , 103). Rose‐Mary Sargent legitimized this view twenty years ago (Sargent , 70). However, I am not aware that any other authoritative authors would have done so since then. While Jan C. Wojcik makes clear the extent to which Boyle's Sceptical Chymist of 1661 has long been misinterpreted in order to justify a “modern” view of Boyle's corpuscularianism (Wojcik ,133), he notes in the preface to his study that “‘the father of modern chemistry’ was not a scientist who dabbled in alchemy on the side” (Wojcik , ix). I have associated myself with this view (von Greyerz ), particularly in connection with Boyle's reliance on alchemical insights offered by the Wittenberg medical professor Daniel Sennert (1572–1637).
The new view of the place of Sennert in the seventeenth‐century history of science has been driven home by William Newman in a number of articles and, in particular, by his incisive study Atoms and Alchemy (2006). In this monograph, Newman squarely places the corpuscular theories of Sennert and Boyle in a tradition going back as far as the late thirteenth century, when an author who named himself “Geber,” and whom he identifies as Paul of Taranto, wrote his Summa perfectionis (Newman , 72, 274f.; Newman , 26; Klein ). At the same time, Newman is able to demonstrate that, as far as the early modern period is concerned, this was an experimental tradition. Boyle certainly had no qualms in combining a literal and an allegorical reading of the book of nature.
In short, if we look at the long‐term development of modern science, it appears plausible to me that a literal reading of the Bible and the Book of Nature was highly influential. However, as far as the outcome of late seventeenth‐century mechanical philosophy is concerned, it is not really clear to me whether we should accord priority to this factor. Alchemy was by definition an allegorical way of approaching the secrets of nature and it unquestionably played an important role in shaping the scientific thought of the two most prominent exponents of Britain's late seventeenth‐century science, Boyle and Newton. To conclude that the concern for these and other contemporary scientists for hermeticism, alchemy, and biblical prophecies simply were “indicative of an unconscious reluctance to admit the failure of the old world picture” (Harrison , 271) does not really do justice to the relevant research of the last decades.
THE ROLE OF VIRTUOSO COLLECTORS
Who are “the relevant historical actors?” Peter Harrison refers to them in passing (52), and seems to take the answer for granted. However, in methodological terms this raises important questions regarding the conceptual approach the author has opted for. In the present context, this is so because the methodological orientation of conceptual history or Begriffsgeschichte initiated during the 1960s by Quentin Skinner in Britain and Reinhart Koselleck in Germany tends to privilege knowledge claims over the process of knowledge making (Koselleck ; Skinner ), because the contextuality they invoke is above all of a textual kind.
To be sure, the most unhelpful discussions of newly published works are those that try to tell the author that he should have written a different book. As I have no objection to Harrison's highlighting the seventeenth century as a watershed in the development of the relationship of science and religion, I will thus limit myself in this second part of my essay to opening the spectrum of the relevant historical actors who participated in this transformation.
In 1685, when John Aubrey (1626–1697) completed his Naturall Historie of Wiltshire, his book (which remained unpublished) contained a compilation of observations in and of nature, as well as accounts of the experiences of the preternatural and supernatural. This included stories of witches, the apparition of ghosts, confirmations of the unexplainable fate of some families and of divine omens. It was not a blind compilation; Aubrey qualified a few of them as “impostures” (Hunter , 102f.). John Aubrey was an early member of the Royal Society and he used some of the regular meetings to inform those present about his observations. These concerned improvements in agriculture, all kinds of recipes, the tide, winds, fog, earthquakes, monsters, and fossils. At one point he also enlightened the assembly about an excellent beer produced without hops (Hunter , 96). Another virtuoso to be mentioned here, likewise an early member of the Royal Society, was Elias Ashmole (1617–1692). He can be seen as somebody who tried to carry on the magical tradition established by John Dee, but, at the same time, he was also a collector of plants, minerals, coins, and other curiosities. He inherited the remarkable cabinet of curiosities assembled by John Tradescant the elder (d. 1638) and his descendants, which formed the basic collection of the Ashmolean Museum founded in 1682. Its first curator was Robert Plot (1640–1696) (Hunter , 142; MacGregor , 149–52).
Robert Plot was the author of the Natural History of Oxford‐shire, which was published in 1677. Michael Hunter has categorized this History as a typical example of the almost blind empiricism of some of the virtuosi among the early members of the Royal Society who engaged in a Baconian sort of collecting (Hunter , 93f.). Elsewhere he has qualified Bacon's conception of collections as a basis for natural history, “the store of data from which hypotheses were to be inductively derived,” as “perhaps his [Bacon's] most significant methodological legacy to seventeenth century science” (Hunter , 18; see also Daston and Park , 220–31). At first sight this seems to contradict Hunter's view of Plot's History, but in fact it does not because, first, even the most inchoate collections contained, as it were, the seeds of later taxonomy, and secondly, for many contemporary virtuosi they confirmed their impression of the marvels of God's creation. I do not share Harrison's largely negative view of these efforts, as he inherently tends to judge them from the vantage point of historically more recent taxonomies (Harrison , 90f.). The search for taxonomic order became evident when, in 1669, the botanist Thomas Willisel was sent out into the country by the Royal Society to collect objects that could fill lacunae in the Society Repository (Hunter , 164).
From natural histories we are turning to an only very slightly different context. Contemporary cabinets of curiosities, such as the Repository, and the early natural histories were close relatives. Cabinets of curiosities served as a theatrum memoriae with increasingly encyclopedic aspirations from about 1700 onwards (MacGregor , 155f.) and, before that time, helped the beholder “to understand God's creation,” such as, for example, King Gustavus Adolphus's cabinet, which closely connected the book of nature with Scripture (Boström , 95, 101; Daston and Park , 255–60). The Bible was represented by innumerable illustrations which were joined to the collection's objects. In mid‐August 1657, the architect Joseph Furttenbach (1591–1667), a staunch Lutheran, employed a local cabinetmaker to construct a model of Noah's Ark for his Kunstkammer. This was subsequently inspected by “ecclesiastical and lay persons of high and low estate” who discussed the model's pros and cons and, in some cases, the owner had to defend himself and the craftsman, that they had had no intention actually to imitate God's work (Furttenbach , 250). Furttenbach, councilor of the imperial city of Ulm, was evidently very proud of his cabinet of curiosities, not least because it attracted many local as well as foreign visitors (Siebenhüner ). It was still relatively rare to allow the general public access to one's collection; in England at the time it was only the Tradescants who did so (MacGregor , 150).
In The Advancement of Learning (1605), Bacon distinguished between three kinds of natural history: “of Nature in Course; of Nature Erring, or Varying; and of Nature Altered or wrought, that is History of Creatures, History of Marvailes, and History of Arts.” He observed that there were enough works concerning the normal course of nature, but complained that there existed “no sufficient, or competent Collection of the Workes of Nature which have a Digression or Deflection from the ordinary course of Generations, Productions, and Motions” (Bacon , 105). Events in nature that digressed from its ordinary course needed to be examined and described systematically. “A substantiall and severe Collection of the Heteroclites or Irregulars of nature, well examined and described I finde not: specially not with due reiection of fables, and popular Errrours […]” (Bacon , 105).
In his Micrographia of 1665, Robert Hooke noted in the preface in Baconian style that natural philosophers must not only study the common course of nature, but also its modifications, increases, and deviations, especially in areas where nature, as it were, tries to remain undiscovered: “The footsteps in Nature are to be trac'd, not only in her ordinary course, but when she seems to be put to her shifts, to make many doublings and turnings, and to use some kind of art in indeavouring to avoid our discovery” (Hooke , Preface). To the overwhelming majority of the people involved in these discussions it was perfectly clear that nature is God's creation. It is necessary to underline this fact because many physico‐theologians from the mid‐seventeenth century onward made it their duty to denounce atheists in a sort of unisono refrain and in keeping within a tradition already prominent in the first half of the century (Hunter ; Wojcik , 77f., n. 5).
In 1664, Henry Power, likewise a member of the early Royal Society, explicitly invoked Bacon's authority in his treatise on Experimental Philosophy in a tone reminiscent of New Atlantis:
God as master craftsman is a frequent theme in physico‐theological treatises which I will address in the next section. Power identifies the main task of “onely the Experimental and Mechanical Philosopher … to find the various turnings and mysterious process of this divine Art, in the management of this great Machine of the World.” He accuses the “old Dogmatists and notional Speculators” not to have gone to the trouble of getting to the bottom of things, and, as a result, not to understand more about nature “than a rude Countrey‐fellow does of the Internal Fabrick of a Watch” (Power , 193).These are the days that must lay a new Foundation of a more magnificent Philosophy, never to be overthrown: that will Empirically and Sensibly canvass the Phænomena of Nature, deducing the Causes of things from such Originals in Nature, as we observe are producible by Art, and the infallible demonstration of Mechanicks …. For Art, being the Imitation of Nature (or, Nature at Second‐Hand) it is but a sensible expression of Effects, dependent on the same (though more remote Causes;). … I think it is no Rhetorication to say, That all things are Artificial; for Nature it self is nothing elso but the Art of God. (Power , 192f.)
There are parallels between the research agenda of a Baconian sort of collecting in natural history and natural philosophy on one hand, and contemporary theology on the other. In the late 1650s, the Presbyterian minister Matthew Poole (c. 1624–1679) initiated a “Designe for registring of Illustrious Providences” based on the idea that, in the course of a cooperative venture, complete lists of providences could be compiled in every English county and subsequently joined and analyzed by Poole at Syon College. This was not a spillover of comparable Royal Society activities, as has been suggested, because extant letters addressed to Poole as part of his scheme date from 1657–1661 (Thomas , 95, n.1). However, Keith Thomas is certainly not mistaken in noting “the close parallel with the methods used by the scientists of the Royal Society for collecting and classifying natural phenomena.” He adds that “it is worth recalling that Francis Bacon had himself urged the desirability of compiling a definitive history of the workings of providence” (Thomas , 95). Richard Baxter in fact communicated to Poole his desire to internationalize the project (Lamont , 31). Poole's scheme did not come off the ground, but we are reminded of it in the preface to Increase Mather's An Essay for the Recording of Illustrious Providences, published in Boston in 1684.
The foregoing considerations should have highlighted the extent to which, in seventeenth‐century Britain and beyond the Channel, the collecting of Baconian heteroclites in many cases not only served simultaneously natural and religious ends, but also that from today's vantage point it is difficult to separate these approaches when inspecting things at the grassroots level of history, as they were part of one and the same desire to know. The making of knowledge, which collecting as part of the early natural histories or of cabinets of curiosities entailed, made its way into scientific treatises. To name only two examples: John Ray (1627–1705) is known to have exploited Plot's Natural History of Oxford‐shire for useable material (Hunter , 93); and the Zürich physician and scientist Johann Jakob Scheuchzer (1672–1733) entertained an impressive network of correspondents up and down the country for the collection of natural objects and facts and, between 1698 and 1702, drew up an inventory of Zürich's communal cabinet of curiosities (Rütsche ) with the aim of systematizing knowledge, comparable to similar efforts then undertaken in England by John Woodward, Hans Sloane, and others (MacGregor , 155–58; Flubacher , ch. 4). In considering such practice, it appears difficult to maintain as neat a categorical separation between natural history and natural philosophy as that applied throughout the Territories of Science and Religion. This will become even more evident when we look at physico‐theology in the next section.
PHYSICO‐THEOLOGY
One of the important differences between early modern natural philosophy and its modern successors “is that natural philosophy was unified by its search for a better understanding of God” (Blair , 403). During the last couple of decades of the seventeenth century, natural history and natural theology merged in the new shape of physico‐theology (Vermij , 174). The third and last part of my essay is dedicated to this fascinating, and not sufficiently researched phenomenon. According to Peter Harrison, who pays it due attention,
Harrison distinguishes between physico‐theology and physico‐mathematics highlighted by Isaac Newton's Principia Mathematica Philosophiae Naturalis of 1687. However, I am not sure whether the history of physico‐theology actually bears out this clear‐cut distinction. The Zürich natural historian and scientist Johann Jakob Scheuchzer (1672–1733), for example, simultaneously resorted to both approaches (Kempe , 154f.). On the other hand, it would be clearly wrong to see physico‐theology as a branch of natural theology that actually sought to distance itself entirely from Newton's celestial mechanics and to favor a purely a posteriori approach, as Fritz Krafft has suggested (Krafft , 77). Perhaps it might be more appropriate to distinguish between two forms of argument within physico‐theology, namely cosmic and physical. Neal C. Gillespie has argued that Robert Boyle distrusted the cosmic argument because it implied the risk that simple objects it described could be regarded as a result of chance in terms of their origin and operation. Boyle, like many other physico‐theologians “was concerned about the ability of men to know the objects on which they based their natural theology” (Gillespie , 27). Where this kind of specific experience resulted in arguing for the divine design of a specific object, the argument was based on final causes. This did not agree with Cartesian physics, which rejected final causes, but was perfectly compatible with the new experimental science (Vermij , 177).it reflects the conviction that what natural philosophers study is God's activity, both his direct causal activity and his design of the creatures. This is because divine causation is now considered to be more or less identical to natural causation, and because the theological significance of the creatures is no longer understood allegorically, but in terms of the way in which they have been designed. (Harrison , 110)
When looking at the period from about 1650 to 1750, we can distinguish four specific genres, and possibly even more. On the European continent the argument from design clearly was the dominating genre. The number of acrido‐, bronto‐, insecto‐, litho‐, testaceo‐theologies, and so on that came off the presses is simply astounding. These treatises by and large concentrated on an individual creature or object, whereas much fewer physico‐theological works (unsuccessfully) tried to encompass all of God's creation, such as, for example, the Dutch physician Bernard Nieuwentijt's Het regt gebruik der Werelt beschowingen […] of 1715 (translated as The religious philosopher: or, The right use of contemplating the works of the creator, London 1718) or the Swiss physician Johann Jakob Scheuchzer's Kupfer‐Bibel […] or Physica Sacra of 1731–1735 (Sheehan , 50–60). Other physico‐theologians overstepped the boundary between revealed religion and natural philosophy and consecrated studies to immortality and the resurrection (Vidal ). I would call this a third, clearly distinguishable genre, albeit practiced by only relatively few authors. The many writings triggered in Britain and on the continent by Thomas Burnet's The Sacred Theory of the Earth, dealing with the shape of the earth from creation via the deluge to the apocalypse (Latin: 1681/1689; English, 1684/1690), constitute a fourth, clearly distinguishable genre.
Harrison has argued that the Cambridge Platonists in particular encouraged such an extension of the purview of physico‐theology and that this transcended the traditional topics of natural theology. He has concluded that “for this period, then, physico‐theology was not a sub‐set of natural theology” (Harrison , 175). I will return to this question at the end of this section.
For many physico‐theologians rational explanations guided by the scriptural knowledge of final causes were not an end in itself; they aimed, at the same time, at a worship of the wonders of nature. Among the early exponents of the movement, John Ray provided a model for this in The Wisdom of God Manifested in the Works of Creation (1691). In the germanophone world this was celebrated especially by physico‐theological poets, such as the Hamburg councilor Bartold Hinrich Brockes (1680–1747) (Brockes ; Fry ) or the Swiss physician and natural philosopher Albrecht von Haller (1708–1777) in his poem The Alps (1729), which expresses a sense of awe in front of the sublimity (Erhabenheit) of God's creation (Haller ). Elsewhere, God is repeatedly praised as the master‐artist or master‐craftsman (Stebbins , 33). This pedagogical intention inherent in much of this literature can be seen in the fact that the great majority of it appears in the vernacular and that authors who began writing in Latin eventually opted for the vernacular.
Across the Europe of the last third of the seventeenth century, there was a general learned tendency to forget about the punishing God of Baroque religious culture in favor of praising his goodness, as well as the usefulness of his creation for mankind (cf. Harrison , 161–69). While some mathematicians, including Newton, continued to calculate the precise date of the end of the world (Popkin ), others, like the Platonist Henry More, envisaged a relatively smooth transition from the present to a millenarian future without any real apocalyptic caesura (van den Berg ). Eschatology, based on an allegorical reading of the relevant chapters of the Bible, was losing its appeal. This was one of the reasons why Burnet's Sacred Theory of the Earth sparked off a controversy (Stewart , 33–41) and urged his opponents even more to prove the usefulness of creation and of biblical wonders, such as the deluge and its consequences. This party was later to be called the deluvianists (John Woodward, Johann Jakob Scheuchzer, Jakob Wilhelm Feuerlein, and others; Kempe ; , 73–109).
When physico‐theologians praised God's wisdom and goodness (Güte rather than Gnade [grace]) they had in mind a much more predictable divine being than the sixteenth‐century reformers. This is mainly what their unwavering belief in God's special providence expressed. In Britain, this culminated in the work of Newton and the Newtonians. The doctrine of providence articulated in William Derham's seminal Physico‐Theology of 1713, which was soon thereafter translated into several other European languages, was “based on a precise understanding of Newton's own contribution to the role of God in the world” (Stewart , 53); “the regularities of nature were a manifestation of the continuous and direct activity of God” (Harrison , 79). However, this should not be understood in the sense that Newton identified God with natural law: “There is no such thing as what men commonly call the course of nature. It is nothing else but the will of God producing certain effects in a continued, regular, constant and uniform manner,” is how Samuel Clarke put it as Newton's amanuensis in the famous controversy with Leibniz (quoted in Brooke , 183). Nothing could be more historically wrong than to assume that the providentialism of the physico‐theologians helped them to cover up their deist convictions (Steiger , 122; pace Michel , 12). On the contrary, almost certainly the majority of their hundreds of treatises explicitly and often harshly attacked deism and atheism (Gillespie , 23f.; Trepp , 334). It would be exceedingly difficult to detect any deistic propensities in such works as Walter Charleton's The Darkness of Atheism Dispelled by the Light of Nature. A Physico‐Theological Treatise (1652), or Bernard Nieuwentijt's Het regt gebruik der Werelt beschowingen, ter overtuiginge van Ongodisten en ongelovingen (1715) [Ongodisten are atheists, ongelovingen unbelievers], to name only two out of countless possible examples.
In publishing his Delectus Argumentorum et Syllabus scriptorum qui Veritatem Religionis Christianae adversus Atheos, Epicureos, Deistas seu Naturalistas, Idololatras, Judaeos et Muhammedanos lucubrationibus suis asseruerunt (Selection of arguments and list of authors who by their labors have served the truth of the Christian religion against atheists, Epicureans, deists or naturalists, idolaters, Jews, and Muslims) in 1725, Johann Albert Fabricius, arguably the founding father of German physico‐theology, joined the Boyle lecturers to whom Boyle's will of 18 July, 1691, assigned the task of “proving the Christian religion against notorious Infidels, viz. Atheists, Theists [meaning Deists—KvG], Pagans, Jews, and Mahometans, not descending lower to any controversies, that are among Christians themselves” (Hunter , 239–41). Many, but by no means all, Boyle lecturers addressed physico‐theological themes or Newtonian physico‐theology. However, in the end, most of them helped to internationalize a chiefly Newtonian brand of natural theology that saw Newton “as a guarantor of [its] scientific accuracy” and underlined “the importance of the lawfulness of creation” (Mandelbrote , 90).
The internationalization of natural theology becomes most visible in the production of physico‐theological works. In what follows, I will limit myself to some preliminary remarks on seventeenth‐ and eighteenth‐century book production based on library catalogues from Britain, France, Germany, the Netherlands, and Switzerland. Titles by William Derham and John Ray are the absolute front‐runners. In Britain, between 1713 and 1768, Derham's Physico‐Theology went through thirteen editions, which were followed by at least four “new editions” between 1768 and 1798. The treatise soon appeared in a French translation, which was published in three editions between 1726 and 1732, followed by a Dutch translation (1728) and a German translation published in three editions between 1730 and 1764. Derham's Astro‐Theology appeared in Britain in thirteen editions between 1715 and 1769. A Dutch translation was published in 1728 and a French translation, likewise printed in Holland, a year later. Another late French version appeared in Zürich in 1760. In 1728, as well, Johann Albert Fabricius, that indefatigable promoter of British physico‐theology on the continent, saw a German translation through the press, which (1728–1739) had three editions and was republished in Hamburg again in 1765.
In Britain, there were thirteen editions of John Ray's The Wisdom of God Manifested in the Works of the Creation between 1691 and 1756, and additional print runs thereafter in Glasgow, Aberdeen, and Edinburgh between 1768 and 1798. A French translation appeared in Utrecht in 1714 and a second French edition by the same publisher in 1729. A German translation by Caspar Calvör followed at Goslar in 1717–1718. There also was a Dutch translation, first published in Amsterdam in 1768 and, under a slightly different title, by the same publisher, in 1769. Another very popular work was Ray's Three physico‐theological discourses …, originally entitled Miscellaneous Discourses concerning the Dissolution and Changes of the World (1692), which had its fourth edition in London in 1732. This was immediately translated into Dutch (1694) and reedited in Rotterdam in 1719. There was also a German translation, first published in Hamburg under the picturesque title Sonderbahres Klee‐Blätlein … (curious clover‐leaf), and republished under different titles in Leipzig in 1732 and 1756.
Samuel Clarke's Boyle lecture A Demonstration of the Being and Attributes of God, more particularly in answer to Mr. Hobbs, Spinoza, and their followers went through ten editions in Britain between 1705 and 1767. A French version was published in Amsterdam in 1717, and again in 1727–1728. Not all English‐language treatises were translated directly into other European vernaculars. In the case of some of the writings of Robert Boyle we can observe a different pattern. Several of them, which had been published in English, such as, for example, The Excellency of Theology compar'd with Natural Philosophy (1674) or Some motives and incentives to the love of God (1663), appeared in Geneva in a Latin version in 1696 and 1693, respectively. A German version of both Latin tracts was subsequently published at the Press of the Halle orphanage in 1708. This printing press was run by the Halle Lutheran Pietists, and the publication of Boyle's texts speaks to their doctrinal openness.
Although the history of the major publications of the physico‐theological movement between 1650 and the later eighteenth century demonstrates that the initial stimulus originated in Britain and spread from there to the continent, this did not remain a one‐way road from West to East. However, few continental physico‐theological works made it all the way to the British Isles in the form of translations. Some works of the Dutchmen Jan Swammerdam and Bernard Nieuwentijt are exceptions to this rule. Swammerdam's original Historia Insectorum Generalis (1669) appeared in a French translation in 1682 at Utrecht. His major heritage, the Biblia Naturae, with a foreword by Hermann Boerhaave, published in two volumes in Leiden in 1737–1738, was translated into English by Thomas Flloyd and published in London in 1758. Six years earlier a German translation had appeared in Leipzig. The mathematician and physician Bernard Nieuwentijt's influential Het regt gebruik der werelt beschouwingen … of 1715 appeared in an English translation by John Chamberlayne three years later, and was republished in 1724. A French translation appeared in 1725 and again in 1727. The first German translation dates from 1732 and a second one was published at Jena in 1747.
Again, these bibliographical observations are preliminary. Further research will have to look into the operations of the individual printers and the quality of the translations. What the last paragraphs tentatively convey is a sense of the intensity and the excitement of the transnational physico‐theological discussion especially during the last decades of the seventeenth century and the first half of the eighteenth century. A study of the complementary correspondence networks would undoubtedly confirm this impression. Such studies have so far concentrated on individual cases or have been undertaken within a national context (e.g., Boscani Leoni , ). Clearly, we are looking at an intellectual and religiocultural movement involving at the same time natural philosophers of some renown as well as an army of virtuosi. The size of the latter is mirrored, for example, by the hundreds of treatises demonstrating God's existence by design that appeared in the German‐speaking world of the eighteenth century.
Several germanophone scholars of the last seventy years, beginning with Wolfgang Philipp's dissertation of 1957 (Philipp 1957, , 1250–53) have claimed that early modern physico‐theology is part of a tradition reaching back all the way to the church fathers (Waschkies , 164f.; Michel , 87–89), or they have located its inception in the Reformation or the immediate post‐Reformation period (Krafft , 81; Trepp ). Sara Stebbins was right in criticizing Philipp's undiscriminating attempt to label everything “physico‐theological” that discussed the relationship of religion and science, and she warned that the historical continuities, in which early modern physico‐theological authors placed themselves, should not be taken for granted (Stebbins , 63f.). Peter Harrison, too, has argued convincingly that early modern considerations of contrivance and design should not simply be regarded as “the continuation of a medieval tradition of natural theology with a better and more objectively established data set. Rather, it was the institution of a new approach to nature that was at once more modest and more ambitious than the theologies of nature that preceded it” (Harrison , 113f.) In a similar vein, Michael Kempe has located early modern physico‐theology within a chronological frame spanning 130 years, from 1650 to 1780 (Kempe , 155). Although 1780 might be too restrictive as a terminus ad quem in the British case, it does on other hand designate the period in which physico‐theology was received most intensely on a European scale. Everywhere the movement increasingly had to face fundamental challenges after about 1750: many exponents of the Enlightenment now looked at the Newtonian universe from Voltaire's vantage point, which left no room for special providence; others had for some time begun to distance themselves from the traditional view of the age of the world. By 1775, the Comte de Buffon judged its age to be approximately 74,047 years (Leclerc , 362). Continuing to assume that God had created all plants and animals and man during the biblical six days of creation was now much more difficult than it had been at the turn of the century.
“The intimacy between science and religion” (Brooke ), manifest in the movement of physico‐theology lasted longer in Britain than in Germany, where Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) dealt it a severe blow. In his Der einzige mögliche Beweggrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseyns Gottes (The only possible reason for a demonstration of the being of God), which went through three editions and four printings between 1763 and 1793, and in his Critique of Pure Reason of 1781, he decisively questioned the ability of physico‐theological demonstrations to prove the existence of an omnipotent, wise, good, and just creator (Brooke , 203–06; Krafft ).
In spite of similar criticism voiced by David Hume, British physico‐theology weathered the challenges of the later eighteenth century better than its German counterpart (Brooke , 209), doubtless aided by the fact that, unlike the European continent, Britain was able to manage the transition to the nineteenth century more smoothly. A series of lectures institutionalized next to the Boyle Lectures to assure the vitality of natural theology (Burnett Lectures, Warburton Lectures, Bampton Lectures), all the way to the eight volumes of Bridgewater Lectures published in 1833, gave expression to the unabating belief of the educated in the necessity of natural theology (Philipp 1957, 32). In the early nineteenth century, these tendencies and developments culminated in the publication of William Paley's enormously popular Natural Theology in 1802.
When Kant addressed the “impossibility of the physico‐theological demonstration” in the Critique of Pure Reason (Kant [1781] ) he turned to a “specific experience” of the things in this present world, their quality and position which could serve as the basis of proving the existence of a supreme being: “Such a demonstration we would call the physico‐theological argument (Beweis)” (Kant [1781] , Transzendentale Dialektik, II, iv, 6). No wonder that Hans‐Joachim Waschkies, a philosopher, could define physico‐theology as a “branch” (Seitenzweig) of natural theology, “which comprises all attempts to demonstrate the existence, or at least the nature, of God independently of the Holy Scriptures or any other revelation” (Waschkies , 172) and that Krafft could claim that the method of physico‐theologians always consists of arguing a posteriori (Krafft , 77).
Although the number of German treatises arguing from design is overwhelming, they do not make up the total of physico‐theological treatises in the German vernacular within the period considered here. But to my knowledge, there are comparatively few germanophone works that try to use evidence gained from the study of the Book of Nature for an explanation of biblical revelation, such as parthenogenesis, the resurrection, the creation and the end of the world, other than Scheuchzer and his fellow “diluvianists,” as well as Nieuwentijt. This clearly went beyond the traditional subject matter of natural theology and, in drawing attention to such phenomena, Harrison is undoubtedly right to conclude that “for this period, then, physico‐theology was not a sub‐set of natural theology” (Harrison , 175). It was more than that: simultaneously a kind of real disenchantment and a celebration of the sublime wonders of creation.
DEDICATION
This essay is dedicated to Hartmut Lehmann in the year of his eightieth birthday.
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
The author wishes to thank Ann Blair and Sundar Henny for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this essay.
References
Bacon, Francis. 1633. The Two Bookes of Sr. Francis Bacon, of the Proficience and Advancement of Learning, Divine and Humane. Oxford, UK: I. L[ichfield].
Blair, Ann. 2006. “Natural Philosophy. ” In The Cambridge History of Science, vol. 3, edited by KatharinePark and LorraineDaston, 365–406. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Boscani Leoni, Simona. 2007. “La ricerca sulla montagna nel Settecento sotto nuove prospettive: il ‘network’ anglo‐elvetico‐alpino.” Histoire des Alpes−Storia delle Alpi−Geschichte der Alpen 12: 201–13.
Boscani Leoni, Simona. 2012. “Vernetzte Welten. Das Korrespondenznetzwerk von Johann Jakob Scheuchzer .” In Natura Sacra: Der Frühaufklärer Johann Jakob Scheuchzer (1672–1733), edited by Urs B.Leu, 131–62. Zug, Switzerland: Achius Verlag.
Boström, Hans‐Olaf. 1985. “Philipp Hainhofer and Gustavus Adolphus's Kunstschrank in Uppsala .” In The Origins of Museums: The Cabinet of Curiosities in Sixteenth‐ and Seventeenth‐Century Europe, edited by OliverImpey and ArthurMacGregor, 90–101. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Brockes, Barthold Heinrich. 1965. Auszug der vornehmsten Gedichte aus dem Irdischen Vergnügen in Gott. Facsimile of the 1738 edn. Stuttgart, Germany: J.B. Metzlersche Verlagsbuchhandlung.
Brooke, John Hedley. 1988. “The God of Isaac Newton .” In Let Newton Be! A New Perspective on His Life and Works, edited by JohnFauvel, RaymondFlood, MichaelShortland, and RobinWilson, 169–84. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Brooke, John Hedley. 1991. Science and Religion: Some Historical Perspectives. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Capp, Bernard. 1979. Astrology and the Popular Press: English Almanacs, 1500–1800. London, UK: Faber & Faber.
Caroti, Stefano. 1986. “Melanchthon's Astrology .” In “Astrology hallucinati”: Stars and the End of the World in Luther's Time, edited by PaolaZambelli, 109–21. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.
Clark, Stuart. 1997. Thinking with Demons: The Idea of Witchcraft in Early Modern Europe. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Curry, Patrick. 1989. Prophecy and Power: Astrology in Early Modern England. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.
Daston, Lorraine, and KatharinePark. 1998. Wonders and the Order of Nature. New York, NY: Zone Books.
Dobbs, Betty Jo Teeter. 1975. The Foundations of Newton's Alchemy, or, “The Hunting of the Greene Lyon.” Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Flubacher, Silvia. 2015. Wunderbare Wesen: Die Ordnung der Tierwelt und das Schreiben der Naturgeschichte um 1700. Unpublished PhD thesis, University of Basel.
Fry, Harold B.1989. Physics, Classics, and the Bible: Elements of the Secular and the Sacred in Barthold Heinrich Brockes "Irdisches Vergnügen in Gott,” 1721. New York, NY: Peter Lang.
Furttenbach, Joseph. 2013. “Lebenslauff .” Selbstzeugnisse der Neuzeit, vol. 22, edited by KasparvonGreyerz, KimSiebenhüner, and RobertoZaugg, 1652–64. Köln, Germany: Böhlau.
Gillespie, Neal C.1987. “Natural History, Natural Theology, and Social Order: John Ray and the ‘Newtonian Ideology.’” Journal of the History of Biology 20(1):1–49.
Golinski, Jan. 1988. “The Secret Life of an Alchemist .” In Let Newton Be! A New Perspective on his Life and Works, edited by JohnFauvel, RaymondFlood, MichaelShortland, and RobinWilson, 147–67. Oxford, UK: Oxford Univ. Press.
Greyerz, Kasparvon. 1996. “Grenzen zwischen Religion, Magie und Konfession aus der Sicht der frühneuzeitlichen Mentalitätsgeschichte .” In Grenzen und Raumvorstellungen: Frontières et conception de l'espace, edited by Guy P.Marchal, 329–42. Zürich, Switzerland: Chronos.
Greyerz, Kasparvon. 1999. “Alchemie Hermetismus und Magie. Zur Frage der Kontinuitäten in der wissenschaftlichen Revolution .” In Im Zeichen der Krise: Religiosität im Europa des 17. Jahrhunderts, edited by HartmutLehmann and Anne‐CharlottTrepp, 415–32. Göttingen, Germany: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Greyerz, Kasparvon. 2012. “Der Umgang mit Hexen in protestantischen Territorien .” In Schwierige Toleranz. Der Umgang mit Andersdenkenden und Andersgläubigen in der Christentumsgeschichte, edited by MarianoDelgado, VolkerLeppin, and DavidNeuhold, 121–41. Fribourg, Germany: Academic Press.
Greyerz, Kasparvon. 2015. “Ort des wissenschaftlichen Forschens und der religiösen Spekulation. Das Labor der Alchemisten im 17. Jahrhundert .” In Orte der europäischen Religionsgeschichte, edited by AdrianHermann and JürgenMohn, 125–44. Würzburg, Germany: Ergon Verlag.
Gunnoe, Charles D.2011. Thomas Erastus and the Palatinate: A Renaissance Physician in the Second Reformation. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill.
Haller, Albrechtvon. 1732. Versuch Schweizerischer Gedichten …. Bern, Switzerland: Niclaus Emanuel Haller.
Harrison, Peter. 1998. The Bible, Protestantism, and the Rise of Natural Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Harrison, Peter. 2005. “Physico‐Theology and the Mixed Sciences: The Role of Theology in Early Modern Natural Philosophy .” In The Science of Nature in the Seventeenth Century, edited by Peter R.Anstey and John A.Schuster, 165–83. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.
Harrison, Peter. [2006] 2011a. “‘Science’ and ‘Religion’: Constructing the Boundaries. ” Journal of Religion 86: 81–106, reprinted 2011 in Religion and Science: Critical Concepts in Religious Studies, edited by Sara FletcherHarding and NancyMorillo, vol. I, 113–36. London, UK: Routledge.
Harrison, Peter. [2006] 2011b. “The Bible and the Emergence of Modern Science .” Science and Christian Belief 18: 115–32), reprinted 2011 in Religion and Science: Critical Concepts in Religious Studies, edited by Sara FletcherHarding and NancyMorillo, vol. I, 197–215. London, UK: Routledge.
Harrison, Peter. 2007. The Fall of Man and the Foundations of Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Harrison, Peter. 2015. The Territories of Science and Religion. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Hooke, Robert. 1665. Micrographia or Some Physiological Descriptions of Minute Bodies made by the Magnifying Glasses, London, UK: John Martyn and James Allestry.
Hunter, Michael. 1975. John Aubrey and the Realm of Learning. London, UK: Duckworth.
Hunter, Michael. 1981. Science and Society in Restoration England. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hunter, Michael. 1985a. “The Problem of ‘Atheism’ in Early Modern England.” Transactions of the Royal Historical Society 35:135–57.
Hunter, Michael. 1985b. “The Royal Society's Repository and its Background .” In The Origins of Museums: The Cabinet of Curiosities in Sixteenth‐ and Seventeenth‐Century Europe, edited by OliverImpey and ArthurMacGregor, 159–68. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Hunter, Michael. 2009. Boyle between God and Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1787. Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1781), 2nd edn. 1787. Facsimile‐reprint, n.d. Leipzig, Germany: Inselverlag.
Kempe, Michael. 1996. “Die Sintfluttheorie von Johann Jakob Scheuchzer: Zur Entstehung des modernen Weltbildes und Naturverständnisses.” Zeitschrift für Geschichtswissenschaft 44:485–501.
Kempe, Michael. 2003. Wissenschaft, Theologie, Aufklärung: Johann Jakob Scheuchzer (1672–1733) und die Sintfluttheorie. Epfendorf, Germany: Biblioteca Academica.
Klein, Joel. 2014. “Chymical Medicine, Corpuscularism, and Controvery: A study of Daniel Sennert's Works and Letters.” Unpublished PhD thesis, Indiana University Bloomington, Bloomington, IN.
Koselleck, Reinhart. 1968. “Vergangene Zukunft der frühen Neuzeit .” In Epirrhosis: Festgabe für Carl Schmitt, edited by HansBarion, Ernst‐WolfgangBöchenförde, and ErnstForsthoff, vol. 2, 549–66. Berlin, Germany: Duncker & Humblot.
Krafft, Fritz. 1999. “…denn Gott schafft nichts umsonst!” Das Bild der Naturwissenschaft vom Kosmos im historischen Kontext des Spannungsfeldes Gott—Mensch—Natur. Münster, Germany: LIT Verlag.
Kusukawa, Sachiko. 1995. The Transformation of Natural Philosophy: The Case of Philip Melanchthon. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Lamont, William M.1979. Richard Baxter and the Millenium: Protestant Imperialism and the English Revolution. London, UK: Croom Helm.
Leclerc, Georges‐Louis, ComtedeBuffon. 1775. “Recherches sur le refroidissement de la Terre et des Planètes .” In Buffon, Histoire naturelle, générale et particulière, supplément, vol. 2. Available at www.buffon.cnrs.fr., 361–515.
MacGregor, Arthur. 1985. “The Cabinet of Curiosities in Seventeenth‐Century Britain .” In The Origins of Museums: The Cabinet of Curiosities in Sixteenth‐ and Seventeenth‐Century Europe, edited by OliverImpey and ArthurMacGregor, 147–58. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Mandelbrote, Scott. 2013. “Early Modern Natural Theologies .” In The Oxford Handbook of Natural Theology, edited by Russell ReManning, 75–99. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Merton, Robert K. [1938] 1978. Science, Technology and Society in Seventeenth Century England. Brighton, UK: Harvester.
Michel, Paul. 2008. Physikotheologie. Ursprünge, Leistung und Niedergang einer Denkform. Neujahrsblatt der Gelehrten Gesellschaft Zürich auf das Jahr 2008. Zürich, Switzerland: Editions à la Carte.
Nagel, Fritz, and SulamithGehr. 2012. “Zürich und Basel im Dialog: Johann Jakob Scheuchzers Korrespondenz mit Johann I Bernoulli .” In Natura Sacra: Der Frühaufklärer Johann Jakob Scheuchzer (1672–1733), edited by Urs B.Leu, 181–207. Zug, Switzerland: Achius Verlag.
Newman, William R.2004. Promethean Ambitions: Alchemy and the Quest to Perfect Nature. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Newman, William R.. 2006. Atoms and Alchemy: Chymistry and the Experimental Origins of the Scientific Revolution. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Philipp, Wolfgang. 1957. Das Werden der Aufklärung in theologiegeschichtlicher Sicht. Göttingen, Germany: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.
Philipp, Wolfgang. 1967. “Physicotheology in the Age of Enlightenment: Appearance and History.” Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 57:1233–67.
Popkin, Richard H.1984. “Predicting, Prophesying, Divining and Foretelling from Nostradamus to Hume.” History of European Ideas 5:117–35.
Power, Henry. 1664. Experimental Philosophy, in Three Books: Containing New Experiments, Microscopical, Mercurial, Magnetical. London, UK: T. Roycroft.
Rütsche, Claudia. 1997. Die Kunstkammer in der Zürcher Wasserkirche: Öffentliche Sammeltätigkeit einer gelehrten Bürgerschaft im 17. und 18. Jahrhundert …. Bern, Switzerland: Peter Lang.
Sargent, Rose‐Mary. 1995. The Diffident Naturalist: Robert Boyle and the Philosophy of Experiment. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Schluchter, Wolfgang. 1981. The Rise of Western Rationalism: Max Weber's Developmental History, translated by Guenther Roth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Schluchter, Wolfgang. 2009. Die Entzauberung der Welt: Sechs Studien zu Max Weber. Tübingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck.
Sharpe, James. 1997. Instruments of Darkness: Witchcraft in England, 1550–1750. London, UK: Penguin Books.
Sheehan, Jonathan. 2003. “From Philology to Fossils: The Biblical Encyclopedia in Early Modern Europe.” Journal of the History of Ideas 64:41–60.
Siebenhüner, Kim. 2013. “Entwerfen, Modelle bauen, ausstellen: Joseph Furttenbach und seine Rüst‐ und Kunstkammer .” In Joseph Furttenbach. Lebenslauff, 1652–1664, edited by KasparvonGreyerz, KimSiebenhüner, and RobertoZaugg, 45–65. Köln, Germany: Böhlau.
Skinner, Quentin. 1969. “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas.” History and Theory 8:3–53.
Stebbins, Sara. 1980. Maxima in Minimis. Zum Empirie‐ und Autoritätsverständnis in der physikotheologischen Literatur der Frühaufklärung. Frankfurt/Main, Germany: Peter D. Lang.
Steiger, Johann Anselm. 2005. “Ist es denn ein Wunder? Die aufgeklärte Wunderkritik. Oder: Von Spinoza zu Reimarus .” In 500 Jahre Theologie in Hamburg: Hamburg als Zentrum christlicher Theologie und Kultur zwischen Tradition und Zukunft …, edited by Johann AnselmSteiger. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.
Stewart, Larry. 1992. The Rise of Public Science: Rhetoric, Technology, and Natural Philosophy in Newtonian Britain, 1660–1750. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Thomas, Keith, 1971. Religion and the Decline of Magic. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons.
Trepp, Anne‐Charlott. 2009. Von der Glückseligkeit alles zu wissen: Die Erforschung der Natur als religiöse Praxis in der Frühen Neuzeit. Frankfurt/Main, Germany: Campus.
Vanden Berg, Johannes. 1988. “Continuity within a Changing Context: Henry More's Millenarianism, Seen against the Background of the Millenarian Concepts of Joseph Mede.” Pietismus und Neuzeit 14:186–203.
Van derMeer, Jitse M., and Richard J.Oosterhoff. 2008. “God, Scripture, and the Rise of Modern Science (1200–1700): Notes in the Margin of Harrison's Hypothesis.” In Nature and Scripture in the Abrahamic Religions: Up to 1700, 4 vols, vol. 2, edited by Jitsevan derMeer and ScottMandelbrote, 363–96. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill.
Vermij, Rienk. 1993. “The Beginnings of Physico‐Theology: England, Holland, Germany .” In Grenz‐Überschreitung …. Festschrift zum 70. Geburtstag von Manfred Büttner, edited by HeynoKattenstedt, 173–84. Bochum, Germany: Brockmeyer.
Vermij, Rienk. 2002. The Calvinist Copernicans: The Reception of the New Astronomy in the Dutch Republic, 1575–1750 . Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Vidal, Fernando. 2003. “Extraordinary Bodies and the Physicotheological Imagination .” In The Faces of Nature in Enlightenment Europe, edited by Lorraine Daston and Gianna Pomata, 61–96. Berlin, Germany: Berliner Wissenschaftsverlag.
Walsham, Alexandra. 1999. Providence in Early Modern England. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Waschkies, Hans‐Joachim. 1988. “Die Physikotheologie al Gegenstand historischer Forschung .” In Geisteshaltung und Umwelt: Festschrift zum 65. Geburtstag von Manfred Büttner, edited by WernerKreisel, 163–81. Aachen, Germany: Alano Verlag.
Webster, Charles. 1975. The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine, and Reform, 1626–1660. London, UK: Duckworth.
Westfall, Richard. 1984. “Newton and Alchemy .” In Occult and Scientific Mentalities in the Renaissance, edited by Brian Vickers, 315–35. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Westman, Robert S.2011. The Copernican Question: Prognostication, Skepticism, and Celestial Order. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Westman, Robert S.2013. “The Copernican Question Revisited: A Reply to Noel Swerdlow and John Heilbron.” Perspectives on Science 21:100–36.
Wojcik, Jan W.1997. Robert Boyle and the Limits of Reason. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.